首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
文章检索
  按 检索   检索词:      
出版年份:   被引次数:   他引次数: 提示:输入*表示无穷大
  收费全文   16篇
  免费   0篇
  国内免费   2篇
力学   3篇
数学   15篇
  2022年   1篇
  2010年   2篇
  2009年   2篇
  2008年   1篇
  2007年   1篇
  2006年   1篇
  2004年   2篇
  2001年   1篇
  1999年   1篇
  1998年   3篇
  1997年   2篇
  1996年   1篇
排序方式: 共有18条查询结果,搜索用时 218 毫秒
1.
The possibility of continuous conjugation of the straightline radial motion of a gas sphere toward the center and away from the center with the motion where the gas in the entire sphere stops simultaneously is shown. The motion is described by an invariant submodel of rank 1. Time reflections allow one to construct a solution that describes a periodic continuous restricted motion of the gas sphere under the action of a piston.  相似文献   
2.
We define two notions for intuitionistic predicate logic: that of a submodel of a Kripke model, and that of a universal sentence. We then prove a corresponding preservation theorem. If a Kripke model is viewed as a functor from a small category to the category of all classical models with (homo)morphisms between them, then we define a submodel of a Kripke model to be a restriction of the original Kripke model to a subcategory of its domain, where every node in the subcategory is mapped to a classical submodel of the corresponding classical model in the range of the original Kripke model. We call a sentence universal if it is built inductively from atoms (including ? and ⊥) using ∧, ∨, ?, and →, with the restriction that antecedents of → must be atomic. We prove that an intuitionistic theory is axiomatized by universal sentences if and only if it is preserved under Kripke submodels. We also prove the following analogue of a classical model‐consistency theorem: The universal fragment of a theory Γ is contained in the universal fragment of a theory Δ if and only if every rooted Kripke model of Δ is strongly equivalent to a submodel of a rooted Kripke model of Γ. Our notions of Kripke submodel and universal sentence are natural in the sense that in the presence of the rule of excluded middle, they collapse to the classical notions of submodel and universal sentence. (© 2007 WILEY‐VCH Verlag GmbH & Co. KGaA, Weinheim)  相似文献   
3.
For a space X, X2 denotes the collection of all non-empty closed sets of X with the Vietoris topology, and K(X) denotes the collection of all non-empty compact sets of X with the subspace topology of X2. The following are known:
ω2 is not normal, where ω denotes the discrete space of countably infinite cardinality.
For every non-zero ordinal γ with the usual order topology, K(γ) is normal iff whenever cf γ is uncountable.
In this paper, we will prove:
(1)
ω2 is strongly zero-dimensional.
(2)
K(γ) is strongly zero-dimensional, for every non-zero ordinal γ.
In (2), we use the technique of elementary submodels.  相似文献   
4.
We correct the proof of Theorem 8 in “Normality and countable paracompactness of hyperspaces of ordinals” [Topology Appl. 154 (2007) 358-362].  相似文献   
5.
There are several ways for defining the notion submodel for Kripke models of intuitionistic first‐order logic. In our approach a Kripke model A is a submodel of a Kripke model B if they have the same frame and for each two corresponding worlds Aα and Bα of them, Aα is a subset of Bα and forcing of atomic formulas with parameters in the smaller one, in A and B, are the same. In this case, B is called an extension of A. We characterize theories that are preserved under taking submodels and also those that are preserved under taking extensions as universal and existential theories, respectively. We also study the notion elementary submodel defined in the same style and give some results concerning this notion. In particular, we prove that the relation between each two corresponding worlds of finite Kripke models AB is elementary extension (in the classical sense) (© 2009 WILEY‐VCH Verlag GmbH & Co. KGaA, Weinheim)  相似文献   
6.
We define a property of substructures of models of arithmetic, that of being length-initial, and show that sharply bounded formulae are absolute between a model and its length-initial submodels. We use this to prove independence results for some weak fragments of bounded arithmetic by constructing appropriate models as length-initial submodels of some given model.  相似文献   
7.
We show that if M is a stable unsuperstable homogeneous structure, then for most κ ? |M|, the number of elementary submodels of M of power κ is 2κ.  相似文献   
8.
A construction of L. Brian Lawrence is extended to show that the -power of every subset of the Cantor set is homogeneous via a continuous translation modulo a dense set. It follows that every zero-dimensional first-countable space has a homogeneous -power.

  相似文献   

9.
In the first part of this paper we let M be a stable homogeneous model and we prove a nonstructure theorem for the class of all elementary submodels of M, assuming that M is ‘unsuperstable’ and has Skolem functions. In the second part we assume that M is an unstable homogeneous model of large cardinality and we prove a nonstructure theorem for the class of all elementary submodels of M.  相似文献   
10.
The purpose of this note is to show that the independence results for sharply bounded arithmetic of Takeuti [4] and Tada and Tatsuta [3] can be obtained and, in case of the latter, improved by the model-theoretic method developed by the author in [2].  相似文献   
设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号