共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 15 毫秒
1.
Luminiţa Simona Vîţă 《Archive for Mathematical Logic》2006,45(3):351-356
A natural extension theorem for strongly continuous mappings, the morphisms in the category of apartness spaces, is proved
constructively.
The author thanks Douglas Bridges and the anonymous referee for their useful suggestions, and the FoRST New Zealand for supporting
her as a Postdoctoral Research Fellow (contract number UOCX0215) during the writing of this paper. 相似文献
2.
Fred Richman 《代数通讯》2013,41(7):2351-2356
In this article, we first present a unified technique in the discussion of the additivity of multiplicative maps on rings with idempotents. We next apply the obtained result to discuss the additivity of surjective elementary maps in rings with idempotents. 相似文献
3.
Jakob G. Simonsen 《Mathematical Logic Quarterly》2005,51(5):532-540
Specker sequences are constructive, increasing, bounded sequences of rationals that do not converge to any constructive real. A sequence is said to be a strong Specker sequence if it is Specker and eventually bounded away from every constructive real. Within Bishop's constructive mathematics we investigate non‐decreasing, bounded sequences of rationals that eventually avoid sets that are unions of (countable) sequences of intervals with rational endpoints. This yields surprisingly straightforward proofs of certain basic results fromconstructive mathematics. Within Russian constructivism, we show how to use this general method to generate Specker sequences. Furthermore, we show that any nonvoid subset of the constructive reals that has no isolated points contains a strictly increasing sequence that is eventually bounded away from every constructive real. If every neighborhood of every point in the subset contains a rational number different from that point, the subset contains a strong Specker sequence. (© 2005 WILEY‐VCH Verlag GmbH & Co. KGaA, Weinheim) 相似文献
4.
5.
It is shown within Bishop's constructive mathematics that, under one extra, classically automatic, hypothesis, a continuous homomorphism from R onto a compact metric abelian group is periodic, but that the existence of the minimum value of the period is not derivable (© 2010 WILEY‐VCH Verlag GmbH & Co. KGaA, Weinheim) 相似文献
6.
Douglas S. Bridges 《Mathematical Logic Quarterly》2008,54(1):12-26
Continuing the study of apartness in lattices, begun in [8], this paper deals with axioms for a product a‐frame and with their consequences. This leads to a reasonable notion of proximity in an a‐frame, abstracted from its counterpart in the theory of set‐set apartness. (© 2008 WILEY‐VCH Verlag GmbH & Co. KGaA, Weinheim) 相似文献
7.
Mark Mandelkern 《Mathematical Logic Quarterly》1993,39(1):213-216
Although classically every open subspace of a locally compact space is also locally compact, constructively this is not generally true. This paper provides a locally compact remetrization for an open set in a compact metric space and constructs a one-point compactification. MSC: 54D45, 03F60, 03F65. 相似文献
8.
Hannes Diener 《Mathematical Logic Quarterly》2008,54(1):49-57
Working within the framework of Bishop's constructive mathematics, we will show that it is possible to define compactness in a more general setting than that of uniform spaces. It is also shown that it is not possible to do this in a topological space. (© 2008 WILEY‐VCH Verlag GmbH & Co. KGaA, Weinheim) 相似文献
9.
Luminia Simona Vî 《Mathematical Logic Quarterly》2003,49(6):550-552
The paper deals with proximal convergence and Leader's theorem, in the constructive theory of uniform apartness spaces. (© 2003 WILEY‐VCH Verlag GmbH & Co. KGaA, Weinheim) 相似文献
10.
Jakob G. Simonsen 《Mathematical Logic Quarterly》2006,52(4):323-330
A metric space is said to be locally non‐compact if every neighborhood contains a sequence that is eventually bounded away from every element of the space, hence contains no accumulation point. We show within recursive mathematics that a nonvoid complete metric space is locally non‐compact iff it is without isolated points. The result has an interesting consequence in computable analysis: If a complete metric space has a computable witness that it is without isolated points, then every neighborhood contains a computable sequence that is eventually computably bounded away from every computable element of the space. (© 2006 WILEY‐VCH Verlag GmbH & Co. KGaA, Weinheim) 相似文献
11.
Satoru Yoshida 《Mathematical Logic Quarterly》2003,49(3):305-315
We prove the Banach‐Steinhaus theorem for distributions on the space ??(?) within Bishop's constructive mathematics. To this end, we investigate the constructive sequential completion (?) of ??(?). 相似文献
12.
Josef Berger 《Mathematical Logic Quarterly》2005,51(2):201-205
We represent continuous functions on compact intervals by sequences of functions defined on finite sets of rational numbers. We call this an exact representation. This enables us to calculate the values of the function arbitrarily exactly, without roundoff errors. As an application we develop a procedure to transfer an exact representation of an increasing function into an exact representation of the corresponding inverse function. (© 2005 WILEY‐VCH Verlag GmbH & Co. KGaA, Weinheim) 相似文献
13.
John L. Bell 《Mathematical Logic Quarterly》1999,45(1):135-143
Some aspects of the theory of Boolean algebras and distributive lattices–in particular, the Stone Representation Theorems and the properties of filters and ideals–are analyzed in a constructive setting. 相似文献
14.
15.
Douglas S. Bridges 《Archive for Mathematical Logic》2009,48(5):437-448
In the informal setting of Bishop-style constructive reverse mathematics we discuss the connection between the antithesis of Specker’s theorem, Ishihara’s principle BD-N, and various types of equicontinuity. In particular, we prove that the implication from pointwise equicontinuity to uniform sequential equicontinuity is equivalent to the antithesis of Specker’s theorem; and that, for a family of functions on a separable metric space, the implication from uniform sequential equicontinuity to uniform equicontinuity is equivalent to BD-N. 相似文献
16.
Douglas S. Bridges 《Mathematical Logic Quarterly》2004,50(3):293-294
It is well known that in Bishop‐style constructive mathematics, the closure of the union of two subsets of ? is ‘not’ the union of their closures. The dual situation, involving the complement of the closure of the union, is investigated constructively, using completeness of the ambient space in order to avoid any application of Markov's Principle. (© 2004 WILEY‐VCH Verlag GmbH & Co. KGaA, Weinheim) 相似文献
17.
Working within Bishop‐style constructive mathematics, we examine some of the consequences of the anti‐Specker property, known to be equivalent to a version of Brouwer's fan theorem. The work is a contribution to constructive reverse mathematics (© 2010 WILEY‐VCH Verlag GmbH & Co. KGaA, Weinheim) 相似文献
18.
Mark Mandelkern 《Mathematical Logic Quarterly》1993,39(1):416-430
This paper studies the metric structure of the space Hr of absolutely summable sequences of real numbers with at most r nonzero terms. Hr is complete, and is located and nowhere dense in the space of all absolutely summable sequences. Totally bounded and compact subspaces of Hr are characterized, and large classes of located, totally bounded, compact, and locally compact subspaces are constructed. The methods used are constructive in the strict sense. MSC: 03F65, 54E50. 相似文献
19.
20.
Robert Lubarsky 《代数通讯》2013,41(4):1644-1649
Walker's cancellation theorem says that, if B ⊕ Z is isomorphic to C ⊕ Z in the category of abelian groups, then B is isomorphic to C. We construct an example in a diagram category of abelian groups where the theorem fails. As a consequence, the original theorem does not have a constructive proof even if B and C are subgroups of the free abelian group on two generators. Both of these results contrast with a group whose endomorphism ring has stable range one, which allows a constructive proof of cancellation and also a proof in any diagram category. 相似文献