首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
相似文献
 共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 15 毫秒
1.
Given two infinite binary sequences A,B we say that B can compress at least as well as A if the prefix-free Kolmogorov complexity relative to B of any binary string is at most as much as the prefix-free Kolmogorov complexity relative to A, modulo a constant. This relation, introduced in Nies (2005) [14] and denoted by ALKB, is a measure of relative compressing power of oracles, in the same way that Turing reducibility is a measure of relative information. The equivalence classes induced by ≤LK are called LK degrees (or degrees of compressibility) and there is a least degree containing the oracles which can only compress as much as a computable oracle, also called the ‘low for K’ sets. A well-known result from Nies (2005) [14] states that these coincide with the K-trivial sets, which are the ones whose initial segments have minimal prefix-free Kolmogorov complexity.We show that with respect to ≤LK, given any non-trivial sets X,Y there is a computably enumerable set A which is not K-trivial and it is below X,Y. This shows that the local structures of and Turing degrees are not elementarily equivalent to the corresponding local structures in the LK degrees. It also shows that there is no pair of sets computable from the halting problem which forms a minimal pair in the LK degrees; this is sharp in terms of the jump, as it is known that there are sets computable from which form a minimal pair in the LK degrees. We also show that the structure of LK degrees below the LK degree of the halting problem is not elementarily equivalent to the or structures of LK degrees. The proofs introduce a new technique of permitting below a set that is not K-trivial, which is likely to have wider applications.  相似文献   

2.
Given a reducibility ?r, we say that an infinite set A is r‐introimmune if A is not r‐reducible to any of its subsets B with |A\B| = ∞. We consider the many‐one reducibility ?m and we prove the existence of a low1 m‐introimmune set in Π01 and the existence of a low1 bi‐m‐introimmune set.  相似文献   

3.
The computable Lipschitz reducibility was introduced by Downey, Hirschfeldt and LaForte under the name of strong weak truth-table reducibility (Downey et al. (2004) [6]). This reducibility measures both the relative randomness and the relative computational power of real numbers. This paper proves that the computable Lipschitz degrees of computably enumerable sets are not dense. An immediate corollary is that the Solovay degrees of strongly c.e. reals are not dense. There are similarities to Barmpalias and Lewis’ proof that the identity bounded Turing degrees of c.e. sets are not dense (George Barmpalias, Andrew E.M. Lewis (2006) [2]), however the problem for the computable Lipschitz degrees is more complex.  相似文献   

4.
In this paper we initiate the study of the ω-Turing reducibility between sequences of sets of natural numbers. We shall prove that the induced degree structure is an extension of the structure of the Turing degrees and that the two structures are closely connected, but different enough. Further we shall prove some definability results for the local theory of the newly defined structure.  相似文献   

5.
6.
We introduce two methods for characterizing strong randomness notions via Martin-Löf randomness. We apply these methods to investigate Schnorr randomness relative to 0?.  相似文献   

7.
The set A is low for (Martin-Löf) randomness if each random set is already random relative to A. A is K-trivial if the prefix complexity K of each initial segment of A is minimal, namely . We show that these classes coincide. This answers a question of Ambos-Spies and Ku?era in: P. Cholak, S. Lempp, M. Lerman, R. Shore, (Eds.), Computability Theory and Its Applications: Current Trends and Open Problems, American Mathematical Society, Providence, RI, 2000: each low for Martin-Löf random set is . Our class induces a natural intermediate ideal in the r.e. Turing degrees, which generates the whole class under downward closure.Answering a further question in P. Cholak, S. Lempp, M. Lerman, R. Shore, (Eds.), Computability Theory and Its Applications: Current Trends and Open Problems, American Mathematical Society, Providence, RI, 2000, we prove that each low for computably random set is computable.  相似文献   

8.
We prove that if S is an ω-model of weak weak König’s lemma and , is incomputable, then there exists , such that A and B are Turing incomparable. This extends a recent result of Ku?era and Slaman who proved that if S0 is a Scott set (i.e. an ω-model of weak König’s lemma) and AS0, Aω, is incomputable, then there exists BS0, Bω, such that A and B are Turing incomparable.  相似文献   

9.
Let A be a contraction on a Hilbert space H. The defect index dA of A is, by definition, the dimension of the closure of the range of I-AA. We prove that (1) dAn?ndA for all n?0, (2) if, in addition, An converges to 0 in the strong operator topology and dA=1, then dAn=n for all finite n,0?n?dimH, and (3) dA=dA implies dAn=dAn for all n?0. The norm-one index kA of A is defined as sup{n?0:‖An‖=1}. When dimH=m<, a lower bound for kA was obtained before: kA?(m/dA)-1. We show that the equality holds if and only if either A is unitary or the eigenvalues of A are all in the open unit disc, dA divides m and dAn=ndA for all n, 1?n?m/dA. We also consider the defect index of f(A) for a finite Blaschke product f and show that df(A)=dAn, where n is the number of zeros of f.  相似文献   

10.
11.
We investigate the index sets associated with the degree structures of computable sets under the parameterized reducibilities introduced by the authors. We solve a question of Peter Cholakand the first author by proving the fundamental index sets associated with a computable set A, {e : W e q u A} for q∈ {m, T} are Σ4 0 complete. We also show hat FPT(≤ q n ), that is {e : W e computable and ≡ q n ?}, is Σ4 0 complete. We also look at computable presentability of these classes. Received: 13 July 1996 / Revised version: 14 April 2000 / Published online: 18 May 2001  相似文献   

12.
If r is a reducibility between sets of numbers, a natural question to ask about the structure ? r of the r-degrees containing computably enumerable sets is whether every element not equal to the greatest one is branching (i.e., the meet of two elements strictly above it). For the commonly studied reducibilities, the answer to this question is known except for the case of truth-table (tt) reducibility. In this paper, we answer the question in the tt case by showing that every tt-incomplete computably enumerable truth-table degree a is branching in ? tt . The fact that every Turing-incomplete computably enumerable truth-table degree is branching has been known for some time. This fact can be shown using a technique of Ambos-Spies and, as noticed by Nies, also follows from a relativization of a result of Degtev. We give a proof here using the Ambos-Spies technique because it has not yet appeared in the literature. The proof uses an infinite injury argument. Our main result is the proof when a is Turing-complete but tt-incomplete. Here we are able to exploit the Turing-completeness of a in a novel way to give a finite injury proof. Received: 22 January 1999 / Revised version: 12 July 1999 / Published online: 21 December 2000  相似文献   

13.
Downey and Remmel have completely characterized the degrees of c.e. bases for c.e. vector spaces (and c.e. fields) in terms of weak truth table degrees. In this paper we obtain a structural result concerning the interaction between the c.e. Turing degrees and the c.e. weak truth table degrees, which by Downey and Remmel's classification, establishes the existence of c.e. vector spaces (and fields) with the strong antibasis property (a question which they raised). Namely, we construct c.e. sets such that the c.e. W-degrees below that of A are disjoint from the nonzero c.e. T-degrees below that of A and comparable to that of B. Received: 2 December 1998  相似文献   

14.
By the Telescope Conjecture for Module Categories, we mean the following claim: “Let R be any ring and (A,B) be a hereditary cotorsion pair in Mod-R with A and B closed under direct limits. Then (A,B) is of finite type.”We prove a modification of this conjecture with the word ‘finite’ replaced by ‘countable.’ We show that a hereditary cotorsion pair (A,B) of modules over an arbitrary ring R is generated by a set of strongly countably presented modules provided that B is closed under unions of well-ordered chains. We also characterize the modules in B and the countably presented modules in A in terms of morphisms between finitely presented modules, and show that (A,B) is cogenerated by a single pure-injective module provided that A is closed under direct limits. Then we move our attention to strong analogies between cotorsion pairs in module categories and localizing pairs in compactly generated triangulated categories.  相似文献   

15.
We study the complexity of generic reals for computable Mathias forcing in the context of computability theory. The n-generics and weak n-generics form a strict hierarchy under Turing reducibility, as in the case of Cohen forcing. We analyze the complexity of the Mathias forcing relation, and show that if G is any n  -generic with n≥2n2 then it satisfies the jump property G(n−1)TG⊕∅(n)G(n1)TG(n). We prove that every such G has generalized high Turing degree, and so cannot have even Cohen 1-generic degree. On the other hand, we show that every Mathias n-generic real computes a Cohen n-generic real.  相似文献   

16.
17.
We investigate simultaneous solutions of the matrix Sylvester equations AiX-XBi=Ci,i=1,2,…,k, where {A1,…,Ak} and {B1,…,Bk} are k-tuples of commuting matrices of order m×m and p×p, respectively. We show that the matrix Sylvester equations have a unique solution X for every compatible k-tuple of m×p matrices {C1,…,Ck} if and only if the joint spectra σ(A1,…,Ak) and σ(B1,…,Bk) are disjoint. We discuss the connection between the simultaneous solutions of Sylvester equations and related questions about idempotent matrices separating disjoint subsets of the joint spectrum, spectral mapping for the differences of commuting k-tuples, and a characterization of the joint spectrum via simultaneous solutions of systems of linear equations.  相似文献   

18.
In algorithmic randomness, when one wants to define a randomness notion with respect to some non-computable measure λ, a choice needs to be made. One approach is to allow randomness tests to access the measure λ as an oracle (which we call the “classical approach”). The other approach is the opposite one, where the randomness tests are completely effective and do not have access to the information contained in λ (we call this approach “Hippocratic”). While the Hippocratic approach is in general much more restrictive, there are cases where the two coincide. The first author showed in 2010 that in the particular case where the notion of randomness considered is Martin-Löf randomness and the measure λ is a Bernoulli measure, classical randomness and Hippocratic randomness coincide. In this paper, we prove that this result no longer holds for other notions of randomness, namely computable randomness and stochasticity.  相似文献   

19.
The Navier problem is to find a solution of the steady-state Navier-Stokes equations such that the normal component of the velocity and a linear combination of the tangential components of the velocity and the traction assume prescribed value a and s at the boundary. If Ω is exterior it is required that the velocity converges to an assigned constant vector u0 at infinity. We prove that a solution exists in a bounded domain provided ‖aL2(∂Ω) is less than a computable positive constant and is unique if ‖aW1/2,2(∂Ω)+‖sL2(∂Ω) is suitably small. As far as exterior domains are concerned, we show that a solution exists if ‖aL2(∂Ω)+‖au0nL2(∂Ω) is small.  相似文献   

20.
We study Tukey types of ultrafilters on ω, focusing on the question of when Tukey reducibility is equivalent to Rudin-Keisler reducibility. We give several conditions under which this equivalence holds. We show that there are only c many ultrafilters that are Tukey below any basically generated ultrafilter. The class of basically generated ultrafilters includes all known ultrafilters that are not Tukey above [ω1]<ω. We give a complete characterization of all ultrafilters that are Tukey below a selective. A counterexample showing that Tukey reducibility and RK reducibility can diverge within the class of P-points is also given.  相似文献   

设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号