共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 0 毫秒
1.
利用赋值集的随机化方法,在n值Lukasiewicz命题逻辑系统中引入公式的随机真度,证明了随机真度的MP规则、HS规则及交推理规则;同时引入公式间的随机相似度和随机伪距离,建立了随机逻辑度量空间,推导出随机相似度的若干性质,证明了随机逻辑度量空间中逻辑运算的连续性;并在随机逻辑度量空间中提出了三种不同类型的近似推理模式,证明了三种近似推理模式的等价性. 相似文献
2.
Assessing students’ conceptions related to independence of events and determining probabilities from a sample space has been the focus of research in probability education for over 40 years. While we know a lot from past studies about predictable ways students may reason with well-known tasks, developing a diagnostic assessment that can be used by teachers to inform instruction demands the use of familiar and unfamiliar contexts. This paper presents the current work of a research team whose aim is to create a formative concept inventory with strong evidence of validity that uses a psychometric model to confidently predict whether a student exhibits one or more misconception across many items. We illustrate this process in this paper using a particular item with a context of a raffle aimed to measure whether a student reasons with misconceptions related to independence or equiprobability. The results of two aspects of the validity process: cognitive interviews to assess response processes on individual items, and a large-scale administration to examine internal structure of the concept inventory revealed difficulties in assessing students’ reasoning about these key probability concepts and trends in the prevalence of misconceptions across grades. Results can provide guidance for others aiming to develop assessments in mathematics education and also support further possibilities for research into understanding students’ reasoning about independence and sample space. 相似文献
3.
4.
本文在格值命题逻辑系统L(X)研究工作的基础上,借助于L(X)的语法推演规则,针对四种近似推理模型分别提出了几种近似推理方法。 相似文献
5.
AKindofApproximateReasoningPrinciples¥XiTiezhuang(LuoyangTeachersCollege)Abstract:Inthispeper,wereseachthefollowingformofappr... 相似文献
6.
In this paper we prove a bounded translation of intuitionistic propositional logic into basic propositional logic. Our new theorem, compared with the translation theorem in [1], has the advantage that it gives an effective bound on the translation, depending on the complexity of formulas. 相似文献
7.
Robin Giles 《Fuzzy Sets and Systems》1980,4(3):221-234
An interactive computer program is described which implements the procedure proposed in “A Formal System for Fuzzy Reasoning” [1]. The problem in question is that of deciding what conclusions may be drawn in the presence of (posibly conflicting) evidence provided, generally with associated partial degrees of belief, by several sources of differing reliability. In using the program, each piece of evidence is entered as a sentence (using the terms NOT, AND, OR, IMPLIES as necessary), with an associated ‘degree of belief’ and ‘weight’; followed by a tentative conclusion. The system returns the degree(s) of belief and weight(s) which may rationally be attached to the conclusion. Copies of the program, written in FORTRAN IV (870 lines) have been lodged with the program libraries CUBE, DECUS, and SHARE, or may be obtained by writing to the author. 相似文献
8.
9.
Eduardo Mizraji 《Mathematical Logic Quarterly》1996,42(1):27-40
Vector logic is a mathematical model of the propositional calculus in which the logical variables are represented by vectors and the logical operations by matrices. In this framework, many tautologies of classical logic are intrinsic identities between operators and, consequently, they are valid beyond the bivalued domain. The operators can be expressed as Kronecker polynomials. These polynomials allow us to show that many important tautologies of classical logic are generated from basic operators via the operations called Type I and Type II products. Finally, it is described a matrix version of the Fredkin gate that extends its properties to the many-valued domain, and it is proved that the filtered Fredkin operators are second degree Kronecker polynomials that cannot be generated by Type I or Type II products. Mathematics Subject Classification: 03B05, 03B50. 相似文献
10.
Leila Amgoud Caroline DevredMarie-Christine Lagasquie-Schiex 《International Journal of Approximate Reasoning》2011,52(9):1363-1391
Practical reasoning (PR), which is concerned with the generic question of what to do, is generally seen as a two steps process: (1) deliberation, in which an agent decides what state of affairs it wants to reach - that is, its desires; and (2) means-ends reasoning, in which the agent looks for plans for achieving these desires. The agent’s intentions are a consistent set of desires that are achievable together.This paper proposes the first argumentation system for PR that computes in one step the possible intentions of an agent, avoiding thus the drawbacks of the existing systems. The proposed system is grounded on a recent work on constrained argumentation systems, and satisfies the rationality postulates identified in argumentation literature, namely the consistency and the completeness of the results. 相似文献
11.
Daniel Kayser 《Logica Universalis》2010,4(2):225-239
Reasoning is a goal-oriented activity. The logical steps are at best the median part of a full reasoning: before them, a language has to be defined, and a model of the goal in this language has to be developed; after them, their result has to be checked in the real world with respect to the goal. Both the prior and the subsequent steps can be conducted rationally; none of them has a logical counterpart. Furthermore, Logic aims at prescribing what a correct reasoning is. But correct with respect to what? If the answer is: with respect to truth, the next question is whether the truth in everyday life, physics, economy, is the same as the truth that logicians have in mind. Resorting to Logic is justified only if an idealization in terms of true propositions in the logical sense is compatible with the goal. If such an idealization is legitimate, so is the use of classical Logic. If not, there is no authority forbidding to skew Logic in order to better reflect the nature of the reasoning required for the task. 相似文献
12.
模糊推理全蕴涵算法及其还原性 总被引:15,自引:0,他引:15
模糊推理是模糊控制的逻辑基础,然而通用的模糊推理CRI算法却缺乏严格的逻辑依据,近期问世的模糊推理全蕴涵三I算法有效地改进了CRI算法。本文研究了全蕴涵三I算法的一般计算公式及其还原性问题,并且得到了一些新的算法,也提出了一些新的观点,文献中已有的结果大多数是本文结果的特例。从而为模糊推理提供了一种新方法。 相似文献
13.
14.
基于神经网络的模糊推理 总被引:2,自引:0,他引:2
为了使模糊推理符合推理原则,目前已定义了10多种模糊关系,但各种模糊关系定义都存在一定的缺陷。本文提出的基于神经网络的模糊推理,能很好地符合模糊推理原则。 相似文献
15.
16.
17.
J.B. Paris D. Picado Muio M. Rosefield 《International Journal of Approximate Reasoning》2009,50(8):1151
We treat the sentences in a finite inconsistent knowledge base as assertions that are true with probability at least some primary threshold η and consider as consequences those assertions entailed to have probability at least some secondary threshold ζ. 相似文献
18.
Motivated by the verification of programs with pointer variables, we introduce a temporal logic whose underlying assertion language is the quantifier-free fragment of separation logic and the temporal logic on the top of it is the standard linear-time temporal logic LTL. We analyze the complexity of various model-checking and satisfiability problems for , considering various fragments of separation logic (including pointer arithmetic), various classes of models (with or without constant heap), and the influence of fixing the initial memory state. We provide a complete picture based on these criteria. Our main decidability result is pspace-completeness of the satisfiability problems on the record fragment and on a classical fragment allowing pointer arithmetic. -completeness or -completeness results are established for various problems by reducing standard problems for Minsky machines, and underline the tightness of our decidability results. 相似文献
19.
20.
通过引入概率测度空间,在n值Lukasiewicz命题逻辑系统中提出了满足Kolmogorov公理的命题公式的概率;证明了概率逻辑学基本定理,并将概率逻辑学基本定理推广到了更一般的形式,改进了对推理结论的不可靠度上界的估计;将概率逻辑学的基本方法引入计量逻辑学,建立了更一般的逻辑度量空间;通过概率逻辑学基本定理,证明了逻辑度量空间中概率MP,HS规则,它是真度MP,HS规则的推广. 相似文献