首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
相似文献
 共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 15 毫秒
1.
What is a logic? Which properties are preserved by maps between logics? What is the right notion for equivalence of logics? In order to give satisfactory answers we generalize and further develop the topological approach of [4] and present the foundations of a general theory of abstract logics which is based on the abstract concept of a theory. Each abstract logic determines a topology on the set of theories. We develop a theory of logic maps and show in what way they induce (continuous, open) functions on the corresponding topological spaces. We also establish connections to well-known notions such as translations of logics and the satisfaction axiom of institutions [5]. Logic homomorphisms are maps that behave in some sense like continuous functions and preserve more topological structure than logic maps in general. We introduce the notion of a logic isomorphism as a (not necessarily bijective) function on the sets of formulas that induces a homeomorphism between the respective topological spaces and gives rise to an equivalence relation on abstract logics. Therefore, we propose logic isomorphisms as an adequate and precise notion for equivalence of logics. Finally, we compare this concept with another recent proposal presented in [2]. This research was supported by the grant CNPq/FAPESB 350092/2006-0.  相似文献   

2.
3.
Jay Newhard 《Acta Analytica》2014,29(3):349-361
Michael Lynch has recently proposed an updated version of alethic functionalism according to which the relation between truth per se and lower-level truth properties is not the realization relation, as might be expected, and as Lynch himself formerly held, but the manifestation relation. I argue that the manifestation relation is merely a resemblance relation and is inadequate to properly relate truth per se to lower-level truth properties. I also argue that alethic functionalism does not justify the claim that truth per se exists, or that truth per se is a functional property. Finally, I suggest a replacement for the manifestation relation. I argue that the resulting theory is a strict improvement over alethic functionalism on two counts, but that the improved theory does not justify the claim that truth per se exists. Since no further improvements to the theory are apparent, the prospects for alethic functionalism are dim.  相似文献   

4.
In earlier papers, a rich theory of geometric realizations of an abstract regular polytope has been built up. More recently, a product was described, to add to blending and scaling as a way of combining realizations. This paper introduces an inner product of cosine vectors of normalized realizations, and shows that it has certain orthogonality properties; together with induced cosine vectors, these provide powerful new tools for investigating realizations. The enhanced theory is illustrated by revisiting the realization domains of several polytopes, including the 24-cell and 600-cell.  相似文献   

5.
A refined shell theory is developed for the elastostatics of a moderately thick spherical cap in axisymmetric deformation. This is a two-term asymptotic theory, valid as the dimensionless shell thickness tends to zero.The theory is more accurate than “thin shell” theory, but is still much more tractable than the full three-dimensional theory. A fundamental difficulty encountered in the formulation of shell (and plate) theories is the determination of correct two-dimensional boundary conditions, applicable to the shell solution, from edge data prescribed for the three-dimensional problem. A major contribution of this article is the derivation of such boundary conditions for our refined theory of the spherical cap. These conditions are more difficult to obtain than those already known for the semi-infinite cylindrical shell, since they depend on the cap angle as well as the dimensionless thickness. For the stress boundary value problem, we find that a Saint-Venant-type principle does not apply in the refined theory, although it does hold in thin shell theory. We also obtain correct boundary conditions for pure displacement and mixed boundary data. In these cases, conventional formulations do not generally provide even the first approximation solution correctly. As an illustration of the refined theory, we obtain two-term asymptotic solutions to two problems, (i) a complete spherical shell subjected to a normally directed equatorial line loading and (ii) an unloaded spherical cap rotating about its axis of symmetry.  相似文献   

6.
It has been proved (by S. M. Dudakov and M. A. Taitslin) that the reducibility of some models of a theory implies the second pseudofinite homogeneity property for this theory. We prove the converse, namely, that any theory with the first or the second pseudofinite homogeneity property has a reducible model and, therefore, possesses the second isolation property. This also proves the equivalence of the second isolation property and the second pseudofinite homogeneity property, in contrast to the first pseudofinite homogeneity property, which is more general than the first isolation property (this was established by O. V. Belegradek, A. P. Stolboushin, and M. A. Taitslin).  相似文献   

7.
Adam Hosein 《Acta Analytica》2013,28(4):495-508
Rawls developed a contractualist theory of social justice and Scanlon attempted to extend the Rawlsian framework to develop a theory of rightness, or morality more generally. I argue that there are some good reasons to adopt a contractualist theory of social justice, but that it is a mistake to adopt a contractualist theory of rightness. I begin by illustrating the major shared features of Scanlon and Rawls’ theories. I then show that the justification for these features in Rawls’ theory, the centrality of cooperative fairness to social justice, cannot be used to defend their use in Scanlon’s. Finally, I argue that Scanlon has not provided an adequate alternative defense of these features, and show that they create problems when contractualists try to explain major features of our common-sense morality.  相似文献   

8.
The so-called theory of karma is one of the distinguishing aspects of Hinduism and other non-Hindu south-Asian traditions. At the same time that the theory can be seen as closely connected with the freedom of will and action that we humans supposedly have, it has many times been said to be determinist and fatalist. The purpose of this paper is to analyze in some deepness the relations that are between the theory of karma on one side and determinism, fatalism and free-will on the other side. In order to do that, I shall use what has been described as the best formal approach we have to indeterminism: branching time theory. More specifically, I shall introduce a branching time semantic framework in which, among other things, statements such as “state of affairs e is a karmic effect of agent a”, “a wills it to be the case that e” and “e is inevitable” could be properly represented.  相似文献   

9.
This article proposes a new mathematical theory of communication. The basic concepts of meaning and information are defined in terms of complex systems theory. Meaning of a message is defined as the attractor it generates in the receiving system; information is defined as the difference between a vector of expectation and one of perception. It can be sown that both concepts are determined by the topology of the receiving system. © 2010 Wiley Periodicals, Inc. Complexity 16: 10–26, 2011  相似文献   

10.
It is well known that human psychology determines his/her action and behavior. This fact has not been fully incorporated in game theory. This paper intends to incorporate human psychology in formulating games as people play them. In Part 1 of the paper, we formulate a two-person game by the habitual domain theory and the Markov chain theory. Using the habitual domains theory, we present a new model describing the evolution of the states of mind of players over time, the two-person second-order game. We introduce the concept of the focal mind profile as well as the solution concept of the win-win mind profile. In addition, we provide also a method to predict the average number of steps needed for a game to reach a focal or win-win mind profile. Then, in Part 2 of the paper, under some reasonable assumptions, we derive the possibility theorem stating that it is always possible to reach a win-win mind profile when suitable conditions are satisfied. This research was partially supported by the National Science Council, Taiwan, NSC96-2416-H009-013.  相似文献   

11.
Differential games (DG's) are investigated from a stability point of view. Several resemblances between the theory of optimal control and that of structural stability suggest a differential game approach in which the operators have conflicting interests regarding the stability of the system only. This qualitative approach adds several interesting new features. The solution of a differential game is defined to be the equilibrium position of a dynamical system in the framework of a given stability theory: this is the differential hypergame (DHG). Three types of DHG are discussed: abstract structural DHG, Liapunov DHG, and Popov DHG. The first makes the connection between DG and the catastrophe theory of Thom; the second makes the connection between the value function approach and Liapunov theory; and the third provides invariant properties for DG's. To illustrate the fact that the theory sketched here may find interesting applications, the up-to-date problem of the world economy is outlined.This research was supported by the National Research Council of Canada.  相似文献   

12.
In this paper, we introduce a foundation for computable model theory of rational Pavelka logic (an extension of ?ukasiewicz logic) and continuous logic, and prove effective versions of some related theorems in model theory. We show how to reduce continuous logic to rational Pavelka logic. We also define notions of computability and decidability of a model for logics with computable, but uncountable, set of truth values; we show that provability degree of a formula with respect to a linear theory is computable, and use this to carry out an effective Henkin construction. Therefore, for any effectively given consistent linear theory in continuous logic, we effectively produce its decidable model. This is the best possible, since we show that the computable model theory of continuous logic is an extension of computable model theory of classical logic. We conclude with noting that the unique separable model of a separably categorical and computably axiomatizable theory (such as that of a probability space or an Lp Banach lattice) is decidable.  相似文献   

13.
The recent status of topological geometrodynamics (TGD) is reviewed. One can end up with TGD either by starting from the energy problem of general relativity or from the need to generalize hadronic or superstring models. The basic principle of the theory is `Do not quantize!' meaning that quantum physics is reduced to Kähler geometry and spinor structure of the infinite-dimensional space of 3-surfaces in 8-dimensional space H=M4+×CP2 with physical states represented by classical spinor fields. General coordinate invariance implies that classical theory becomes an exact part of the quantum theory and configuration space geometry and that space-time surfaces are generalized Bohr orbits. The uniqueness of the infinite-dimensional Kähler geometric existence fixes imbedding space and the dimension of the space-time highly uniquely and implies that superconformal and supercanonical symmetries acting on the lightcone boundary δM4+×CP2 are cosmologies symmetries.The work with the p-adic aspects of TGD, the realization of the possible role of quaternions and octonions in the formulation of quantum TGD, the discovery of infinite primes, and TGD inspired theory of consciousness encouraged the vision about TGD as a generalized number theory. The vision leads to a considerable generalization of TGD and to an extension of the symmetries of the theory to include superconformal and Super-Kac-Moody symmetries associated with the group P×SU(3)×U(2)ew (P denotes the Poincaré group) acting as the local symmetries of the theory. Quantum criticality, which can be seen as a prediction of the theory, fixes the value spectrum for the coupling constants of the theory.The proper mathematical and physical interpretation of the p-adic numbers has remained a long-lasting challenge. Both TGD inspired theory of consciousness and the vision about physics as a generalized number theory suggest that p-adic space-time regions obeying p-adic counterparts of the field equations are geometric correlates of mind in the sense that they provide cognitive representations for the physics in the real space-time regions representing matter. Evolution identified as a gradual increase of the infinite p-adic prime characterizing the entire Universe is basic prediction of the theory.S-matrix elements can be identified as Glebsch–Gordan coefficients between interacting and free Super-Kac-Moody algebra representations and it is now possible to give Feynmann rules for the S-matrix in the approximation that elementary particles correspond to the so-called CP2 type extremals.  相似文献   

14.
The authors show that a wide class of Fredholm determinants arising in the representation theory of “big” groups, such as the infinite‐dimensional unitary group, solve Painlevé equations. Their methods are based on the theory of integrable operators and the theory of Riemann‐Hilbert problems. © 2002 Wiley Periodicals, Inc.  相似文献   

15.
Conclusions Thus, for a definite class of significantly nonlinear interaction Lagrangians, we were able to construct, within the framework of nonlocal quantum field theory, the S-matrix of the theory in the form of a convergent perturbation-theory series in the Euclidean formulation of the theory. It was shown earlier that after a continuation into the physical domain, the S-matrix will be unitary in every order of perturbation theory. The next problem is the study of the behavior of the amplitudes of physical processes within the framework of the complete converging series which represents the total S-matrix of the theory.Joint Institute for Nuclear Research. Translated from Teoreticheskaya i Matematicheskaya Fizika, Vol. 2, No. 3, pp. 302–310, March, 1970.  相似文献   

16.
The topic of this paper is the role played by context in art. In this regard I examine three theories linked to the names of J. Levinson, G. Currie and D. Davies. Levinson’s arguments undermine the structural theory. He finds it objectionable because it makes the individuation of artworks independent of their histories. Secondly, such a consequence is unacceptable because it fails to recognise that works are created rather than discovered. But, if certain general features of provenance are always work-constitutive, as it seems that Levinson is willing to claim, these features must always be essential properties of works. On the other hand, consideration of our modal practice suggests that whether a given general feature of provenance is essential or non-essential depends upon the particular work in question or is “work relative”. D. Davies builds his performance theory on the basis of the critical evaluation of Currie’s action-type hypotheses (ATH). Performances, says Davies, are not to be identified with “basic actions” to which their times belong essentially, but with “doings” that permit of the sorts of variation in modal properties required by the work-relativity of modality. He is also a fierce critic of the contextualist account. Contextualism is in his view unable to reflect the fact that aspects of provenance bear upon our modal judgements with variable force.In the second part of the paper I consider Davies’s “modality principle”. Davies is inclined to defend the claim that labels used for designation of works are rigid designators. Such a view offers a ground for discussion about the historicity of art. What has been meant when people claim that art is an historical concept? I argue that any historical theory implies a two-dimensional notion of “art”. At the end of the paper I suggest that Davies should embrace the theory of contingent identity and not the colocationist view about the relationship that exists between a particular artwork and its physical bearer.  相似文献   

17.
In this paper, we study periodic linear systems on periodic time scales which include not only discrete and continuous dynamical systems but also systems with a mixture of discrete and continuous parts (e.g. hybrid dynamical systems). We develop a comprehensive Floquet theory including Lyapunov transformations and their various stability preserving properties, a unified Floquet theorem which establishes a canonical Floquet decomposition on time scales in terms of the generalized exponential function, and use these results to study homogeneous as well as nonhomogeneous periodic problems. Furthermore, we explore the connection between Floquet multipliers and Floquet exponents via monodromy operators in this general setting and establish a spectral mapping theorem on time scales. Finally, we show this unified Floquet theory has the desirable property that stability characteristics of the original system can be determined via placement of an associated (but time varying) system?s poles in the complex plane. We include several examples to show the utility of this theory.  相似文献   

18.
A packing (resp. covering) ? of a normed space X consisting of unit balls is called completely saturated (resp. completely reduced) if no finite set of its members can be replaced by a more numerous (resp. less numerous) set of unit balls of X without losing the packing property (resp. covering property) of ?. We show that a normed space X admits completely saturated packings with disjoint closed unit balls as well as completely reduced coverings with open unit balls, provided that there exists a tiling of X with unit balls. Completely reduced coverings by open balls are of interest in the context of an approximation theory for continuous real‐valued functions that rests on so‐called controllable coverings of compact metric spaces. The close relation between controllable coverings and completely reduced coverings allows an extension of the approximation theory to non‐compact spaces. (© 2004 WILEY‐VCH Verlag GmbH & Co. KGaA, Weinheim)  相似文献   

19.
The Krein-Tannaka duality for compact groups was a generalization of the Pontryagin-van Kampen duality for locally compact Abelian groups and a remote predecessor of the theory of tensor categories. It is less known that it found applications in algebraic combinatorics (“Krein algebras”). Later, this duality was substantially extended: in [29], the notion of involutive algebras in positive vector duality was introduced. In this paper, we reformulate the notions of this theory using the language of bialgebras (and Hopf algebras) and introduce the class of involutive bialgebras and positive 2-algebras. The main goal of the paper is to give a precise statement of a new problem, which we consider as one of the main problems in this field, concerning the existence of dilations (embeddings) of positive 2-algebras in involutive bialgebras, or, in other words, the problem of describing subobjects of involutive bialgebras; we define two types of subobjects of bialgebras, strict and nonstrict ones. The dilation problem is illustrated by the example of the Hecke algebra, which is viewed as a positive involutive 2-algebra. We consider in detail only the simplest situation and classify two-dimensional Hecke algebras for various values of the parameter q, demonstrating the difference between the two types of dilations. We also prove that the class of finite-dimensional involutive semisimple bialgebras coincides with the class of semigroup algebras of finite inverse semigroups.  相似文献   

20.
Subjects presented with scenarios in which they themselves are actors tend to believe that the predictions from affect control theory are the events that really would happen. A laboratory experiment demonstrates that the theory predicts subtle differences in observable behavior as subjects are confronted with different social circumstances.  相似文献   

设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号