首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
相似文献
 共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 31 毫秒
1.
We define two notions for intuitionistic predicate logic: that of a submodel of a Kripke model, and that of a universal sentence. We then prove a corresponding preservation theorem. If a Kripke model is viewed as a functor from a small category to the category of all classical models with (homo)morphisms between them, then we define a submodel of a Kripke model to be a restriction of the original Kripke model to a subcategory of its domain, where every node in the subcategory is mapped to a classical submodel of the corresponding classical model in the range of the original Kripke model. We call a sentence universal if it is built inductively from atoms (including ? and ⊥) using ∧, ∨, ?, and →, with the restriction that antecedents of → must be atomic. We prove that an intuitionistic theory is axiomatized by universal sentences if and only if it is preserved under Kripke submodels. We also prove the following analogue of a classical model‐consistency theorem: The universal fragment of a theory Γ is contained in the universal fragment of a theory Δ if and only if every rooted Kripke model of Δ is strongly equivalent to a submodel of a rooted Kripke model of Γ. Our notions of Kripke submodel and universal sentence are natural in the sense that in the presence of the rule of excluded middle, they collapse to the classical notions of submodel and universal sentence. (© 2007 WILEY‐VCH Verlag GmbH & Co. KGaA, Weinheim)  相似文献   

2.
We introduce a probabilistic extension of propositional intuitionistic logic. The logic allows making statements such as Psα, with the intended meaning “the probability of truthfulness of α is at least s”. We describe the corresponding class of models, which are Kripke models with a naturally arising notion of probability, and give a sound and complete infinitary axiomatic system. We prove that the logic is decidable.  相似文献   

3.
A ring extension AB is depth two if its tensor-square satisfies a projectivity condition w.r.t. the bimodules A A B and B A A . In this case the structures (A ? B A) B and End  B A B are bialgebroids over the centralizer C A (B) and there is a certain Galois theory associated to the extension and its endomorphism ring. We specialize the notion of depth two to induced representations of semisimple algebras and character theory of finite groups. We show that depth two subgroups over the complex numbers are normal subgroups. As a converse, we observe that normal Hopf subalgebras over a field are depth two extensions. A generalized Miyashita–Ulbrich action on the centralizer of a ring extension is introduced, and applied to a study of depth two and separable extensions, which yields new characterizations of separable and H-separable extensions. With a view to the problem of when separable extensions are Frobenius, we supply a trace ideal condition for when a ring extension is Frobenius.  相似文献   

4.
We introduce a notion of relative efficiency for axiom systems. Given an axiom system Aβ for a theory T consistent with S12, we show that the problem of deciding whether an axiom system Aα for the same theory is more efficient than Aβ is II2-hard. Several possibilities of speed-up of proofs are examined in relation to pairs of axiom systems Aα, Aβ, with Aα ? Aβ, both in the case of Aα, Aβ having the same language, and in the case of the language of Aα extending that of Aβ: in the latter case, letting Prα, Prβ denote the theories axiomatized by Aα, Aβ, respectively, and assuming Prα to be a conservative extension of Prβ, we show that if AαAβ contains no nonlogical axioms, then Aα can only be a linear speed-up of Aβ; otherwise, given any recursive function g and any Aβ, there exists a finite extension Aα of Aβ such that Aα is a speed-up of Aβ with respect to g. Mathematics Subject Classification: 03F20, 03F30.  相似文献   

5.
Let A be a matrixp(x) a polynomial. Put B=p(A). It is shown that necessary and sufficient conditions for A to be a polynomial in B are (i) if λ is any eigenvalue of A, and if some elementary divisor of A corresponding to λ is nonlinear, thenp (λ)≠0;and (ii) if λ,μ are distinct eigenvalues of A, then p(λ)p(μ) are also distinct. Here all computations are over some algebraically closed field.  相似文献   

6.
We present an axiomatization for Basic Propositional Calculus BPC and give a completeness theorem for the class of transitive Kripke structures. We present several refinements, including a completeness theorem for irreflexive trees. The class of intermediate logics includes two maximal nodes, one being Classical Propositional Calculus CPC, the other being E1, a theory axiomatized by T → ⊥. The intersection CPC ∩ E1 is axiomatizable by the Principle of the Excluded Middle A V ∨ ?A. If B is a formula such that (T → B) → B is not derivable, then the lattice of formulas built from one propositional variable p using only the binary connectives, is isomorphically preserved if B is substituted for p. A formula (T → B) → B is derivable exactly when B is provably equivalent to a formula of the form ((T → A) → A) → (T → A).  相似文献   

7.
Since in Heyting Arithmetic (HA) all atomic formulas are decidable, a Kripke model for HA may be regarded classically as a collection of classical structures for the language of arithmetic, partially ordered by the submodel relation. The obvious question is then: are these classical structures models of Peano Arithmetic (PA)? And dually: if a collection of models of PA, partially ordered by the submodel relation, is regarded as a Kripke model, is it a model of HA? Some partial answers to these questions were obtained in [6], [3], [1] and [2]. Here we present some results in the same direction, announced in [7]. In particular, it is proved that the classical structures at the nodes of a Kripke model of HA must be models of IΔ1 (PA- with induction for provably Δ1 formulas) and that the relation between these classical structures must be that of a Δ1-elementary submodel. MSC: 03F30, 03F55.  相似文献   

8.
In the first section of this paper we show that i Π1 ≡ W⌝⌝lΠ1 and that a Kripke model which decides bounded formulas forces iΠ1 if and only if the union of the worlds in any (complete) path in it satisflies IΠ1. In particular, the union of the worlds in any path of a Kripke model of HA models IΠ1. In the second section of the paper, we show that for equivalence of forcing and satisfaction of Πm‐formulas in a linear Kripke model deciding Δ0‐formulas it is necessary and sufficient that the model be Σm‐elementary. This implies that if a linear Kripke model forces PEMprenex, then it forces PEM. We also show that, for each n ≥ 1, iΦn does not prove ℋ︁(IΠn's are Burr's fragments of HA.  相似文献   

9.
Let A and B be graph algebras. In this paper we present the notion of an ideal in a graph algebra and prove that an ideal extension of A by B always exists. We describe (up to isomorphism) all such extensions.  相似文献   

10.
In this paper we define a suitable version of the notion of homomorphism for Kripke models of intuitionistic first-order logic and characterize theories that are preserved under images and also those that are preserved under inverse images of homomorphisms. Moreover, we define a notion of union of chain for Kripke models and define a class of formulas that is preserved in unions of chains. We also define similar classes of formulas and investigate their behavior in Kripke models. An application to intuitionistic first-order arithmetic is also given.  相似文献   

11.
We develop stable algorithms for the computation of the Kronecker structure of an arbitrary pencil. This problem can be viewed as a generalization of the well-known eigenvalue problem of pencils of the type λI?A. We first show that the elementary divisors (λ ? α)i of a regular pencil λB?A can be retrieved with a deflation algorithm acting on the expansion (λ ? α)B ? (A ? αB). This method is a straightforward generalization of Kublanovskaya's algorithm for the determination of the Jordan structure of a constant matrix. We also show how to use this method to determine the structure of the infinite elementary divisors of λB?A. In the case of singular pencils, the occurrence of Kronecker indices—containing the singularity of the pencil—somewhat complicates the problem. Yet our algorithm retrieves these indices with no additional effort, when determining the elementary divisors of the pencil. The present ideas can also be used to separate from an arbitrary pencil a smaller regular pencil containing only the finite elementary divisors of the original one. This is shown to be an effective tool when used together with the QZ algorithm.  相似文献   

12.
A depth two extension A | B is shown to be weak depth two over its double centralizer V A (V A (B)) if this is separable over B. We consider various examples and non-examples of depth one and two properties. Depth two and its relationship to direct and tensor product of algebras as well as cup product of relative Hochschild cochains is examined. Section 6 introduces a notion of codepth two coalgebra homomorphism g : CD, dual to a depth two algebra homomorphism. It is shown that the endomorphism ring of bicomodule endomorphisms End D C D forms a right bialgebroid over the centralizer subalgebra g * : D *C * of the dual algebra C *. Dedicated to Daniel Kastler on his eightieth birthday.  相似文献   

13.
If A is a Lie algebroid over a foliated manifold (M, F){(M, {\mathcal {F}})}, a foliation of A is a Lie subalgebroid B with anchor image TF{T{\mathcal {F}}} and such that A/B is locally equivalent with Lie algebroids over the slice manifolds of F{\mathcal F}. We give several examples and, for foliated Lie algebroids, we discuss the following subjects: the dual Poisson structure and Vaintrob's supervector field, cohomology and deformations of the foliation, integration to a Lie groupoid. In the last section, we define a corresponding notion of a foliation of a Courant algebroid A as a bracket–closed, isotropic subbundle B with anchor image TF{T{\mathcal {F}}} and such that B ^ /B{B^{ \bot } /B} is locally equivalent with Courant algebroids over the slice manifolds of F{\mathcal F}. Examples that motivate the definition are given.  相似文献   

14.
A necessary and sufficient condition for a matrix to be stochastically similar to a matrix with equal diagonal elements is obtained Aand B are called Stochastically similar if B=SAS ? 1 where S is quasi-stochastic i.e., all row sums of .S are I. An inverse elementary divisor problem for quasi-stochastic matrices is also considered.  相似文献   

15.
A Kripke model ? is a submodel of another Kripke model ℳ if ? is obtained by restricting the set of nodes of ℳ. In this paper we show that the class of formulas of Intuitionistic Predicate Logic that is preserved under taking submodels of Kripke models is precisely the class of semipositive formulas. This result is an analogue of the Łoś-Tarski theorem for the Classical Predicate Calculus. In Appendix A we prove that for theories with decidable identity we can take as the embeddings between domains in Kripke models of the theory, the identical embeddings. This is a well known fact, but we know of no correct proof in the literature. In Appendix B we answer, negatively, a question posed by Sam Buss: whether there is a classical theory T, such that ℋT is HA. Here ℋT is the theory of all Kripke models ℳ such that the structures assigned to the nodes of ℳ all satisfy T in the sense of classical model theory. Received: 4 February 1999 / Published online: 25 January 2001  相似文献   

16.
Given a commutative ring A equipped with a preordering A+ (in the most general sense, see below), we look for a fractional ring extension (= “ring of quotients” in the sense of Lambek et al. [L]) as big as possible such that A+ extends to a preordering R+ of R (i.e. with AR+ = A+) in a natural way. We then ask for subextensions AB of AR such that A is convex in B with respect to B+ : = BR+. Supported by DFG. A short form of this article has been delivered at the conference Carthapos 2006 at Carthago (Tunisia).  相似文献   

17.
For a faithfully flat extension A/B and a right A-module M, we give a new characterization of the set of descent data on M. Assuming that B is a simple Artinian ring and A/B is H-Galois, for a certain finite dimensional Hopf algebra H, we prove that Sweedler's noncommutative cohomology H 1(H?, A) is trivial as a pointed set.  相似文献   

18.
Summary IfT is a complete theory of Boolean algebra, then we writeAT B to denote that for every cardinal κ and every κ-regular filter over a setI such that the Boolean algebra 2 F I of all subsets ofI reduced byF is a model ofT, the reduced powerA F I isK +-saturated wheneverB F I isK +-saturated. The relation ⊲T generalizes the relation ◃ introduced by Keisler. As in the case of Keisler's ◃ it happens that ⊲T’s are relations between complete theories, i.e. ifA≡B thenAT B andBT A. In this paper some examples of theories which are maximal (minimal) with respect to ⊲T’s are provided and the relations ⊲T are compared with each other. Presented by J. Mycielski  相似文献   

19.
Supposem is a square-free odd integer, andA andB are any two Hadamard matrices of order 4m. We will show thatA andB are equivalent over the integers (that is,B can be obtained fromA using elementary row and column operations which involve only integers).  相似文献   

20.
Let A, B be n × n matrices with entries in a field F. Our purpose is to show the following theorem: Suppose n⩾4, A is irreducible, and for every partition of {1,2,…,n} into subsets α, β with ¦α¦⩾2, ¦β¦⩾2 either rank A[α¦β]⩾2 or rank A[β¦α]⩾2. If A and B have equal corresponding principal minors, of all orders, then B or Bt is diagonally similar to A.  相似文献   

设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号