首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
相似文献
 共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 0 毫秒
1.
The computable Lipschitz reducibility was introduced by Downey, Hirschfeldt and LaForte under the name of strong weak truth-table reducibility (Downey et al. (2004) [6]). This reducibility measures both the relative randomness and the relative computational power of real numbers. This paper proves that the computable Lipschitz degrees of computably enumerable sets are not dense. An immediate corollary is that the Solovay degrees of strongly c.e. reals are not dense. There are similarities to Barmpalias and Lewis’ proof that the identity bounded Turing degrees of c.e. sets are not dense (George Barmpalias, Andrew E.M. Lewis (2006) [2]), however the problem for the computable Lipschitz degrees is more complex.  相似文献   

2.
Downey and Remmel have completely characterized the degrees of c.e. bases for c.e. vector spaces (and c.e. fields) in terms of weak truth table degrees. In this paper we obtain a structural result concerning the interaction between the c.e. Turing degrees and the c.e. weak truth table degrees, which by Downey and Remmel's classification, establishes the existence of c.e. vector spaces (and fields) with the strong antibasis property (a question which they raised). Namely, we construct c.e. sets such that the c.e. W-degrees below that of A are disjoint from the nonzero c.e. T-degrees below that of A and comparable to that of B. Received: 2 December 1998  相似文献   

3.
We study computably enumerable equivalence relations (or, ceers), under computable reducibility ≤, and the halting jump operation on ceers. We show that every jump is uniform join-irreducible, and thus join-irreducible. Therefore, the uniform join of two incomparable ceers is not equivalent to any jump. On the other hand there exist ceers that are not equivalent to jumps, but are uniform join-irreducible: in fact above any non-universal ceer there is a ceer which is not equivalent to a jump, and is uniform join-irreducible. We also study transfinite iterations of the jump operation. If a is an ordinal notation, and E is a ceer, then let E(a) denote the ceer obtained by transfinitely iterating the jump on E along the path of ordinal notations up to a. In contrast with what happens for the Turing jump and Turing reducibility, where if a set X is an upper bound for the A-arithmetical sets then X(2) computes A(ω), we show that there is a ceer R such that RId(n), for every finite ordinal n, but, for all k, R(k)?Id(ω) (here Id is the identity equivalence relation). We show that if a,b are notations of the same ordinal less than ω2, then E(a)E(b), but there are notations a,b of ω2 such that Id(a) and Id(b) are incomparable. Moreover, there is no non-universal ceer which is an upper bound for all the ceers of the form Id(a) where a is a notation for ω2.  相似文献   

4.
If r is a reducibility between sets of numbers, a natural question to ask about the structure ? r of the r-degrees containing computably enumerable sets is whether every element not equal to the greatest one is branching (i.e., the meet of two elements strictly above it). For the commonly studied reducibilities, the answer to this question is known except for the case of truth-table (tt) reducibility. In this paper, we answer the question in the tt case by showing that every tt-incomplete computably enumerable truth-table degree a is branching in ? tt . The fact that every Turing-incomplete computably enumerable truth-table degree is branching has been known for some time. This fact can be shown using a technique of Ambos-Spies and, as noticed by Nies, also follows from a relativization of a result of Degtev. We give a proof here using the Ambos-Spies technique because it has not yet appeared in the literature. The proof uses an infinite injury argument. Our main result is the proof when a is Turing-complete but tt-incomplete. Here we are able to exploit the Turing-completeness of a in a novel way to give a finite injury proof. Received: 22 January 1999 / Revised version: 12 July 1999 / Published online: 21 December 2000  相似文献   

5.
6.
We study the computably enumerable sets in terms of the:  相似文献   

7.
We study the filter ℒ*(A) of computably enumerable supersets (modulo finite sets) of an r-maximal set A and show that, for some such set A, the property of being cofinite in ℒ*(A) is still Σ0 3-complete. This implies that for this A, there is no uniformly computably enumerable “tower” of sets exhausting exactly the coinfinite sets in ℒ*(A). Received: 6 November 1999 / Revised version: 10 March 2000 /?Published online: 18 May 2001  相似文献   

8.
We say that ALRB if every B-random real is A-random—in other words, if B has at least as much derandomization power as A. The LR reducibility is a natural weak reducibility in the context of randomness, and generalizes lowness for randomness. We study the existence and properties of upper bounds in the context of the LR degrees. In particular, we show that given two (or even finitely many) low sets, there is a low c.e. set which lies LR above both. This is very different from the situation in the Turing degrees, where Sacks’ splitting theorem shows that two low sets can join to 0.  相似文献   

9.
We show the undecidability of the -theory of the partial order of computably enumerable Turing degrees.

  相似文献   


10.
We prove the existence of noncomputable low computably enumerable degrees b < a such that b is strongly noncuppable to a in the class R.  相似文献   

11.
12.
13.
It is shown that for any computably enumerable (c.e.) degree , if , then there is a c.e. degree such that (so is lowand is high). It follows from this and previous work of P. Cholak, M. Groszek and T. Slaman that the low and low c.e. degrees are not elementarily equivalent as partial orderings.

  相似文献   


14.
We prove that every non-computable incomplete computably enumerable degree is locally non-cappable, and use this result to show that there is no maximal non-bounding computably enumerable degree. The author was supported by an EPSRC Research Studentship. Mathematics Subject Classification (2000):03D25 Keywords or phrases:Computably enumerable – Degree  相似文献   

15.
Cupping partners of an element in an upper semilattice with a greatest element 1 are those joining the element to 1. We define a congruence relation on such an upper semilattice by considering the elements having the same cupping partners as equivalent. It is interesting that this congruence relation induces a non-dense quotient structure of computably enumerable Turing degrees. Another main interesting phenomenon in this article is that on the computably enumerable degrees, this relation is different from that modulo the noncuppable ideal, though they define a same equivalent class for the computable Turing degree.  相似文献   

16.
We prove that a partially ordered set of all computably enumerable (c. e.) degrees that are the least upper bounds of two superlow c. e. degrees is an upper semilattice not elementary equivalent to the semilattice of all c. e. degrees.  相似文献   

17.
Given two infinite binary sequences A,B we say that B can compress at least as well as A if the prefix-free Kolmogorov complexity relative to B of any binary string is at most as much as the prefix-free Kolmogorov complexity relative to A, modulo a constant. This relation, introduced in Nies (2005) [14] and denoted by ALKB, is a measure of relative compressing power of oracles, in the same way that Turing reducibility is a measure of relative information. The equivalence classes induced by ≤LK are called LK degrees (or degrees of compressibility) and there is a least degree containing the oracles which can only compress as much as a computable oracle, also called the ‘low for K’ sets. A well-known result from Nies (2005) [14] states that these coincide with the K-trivial sets, which are the ones whose initial segments have minimal prefix-free Kolmogorov complexity.We show that with respect to ≤LK, given any non-trivial sets X,Y there is a computably enumerable set A which is not K-trivial and it is below X,Y. This shows that the local structures of and Turing degrees are not elementarily equivalent to the corresponding local structures in the LK degrees. It also shows that there is no pair of sets computable from the halting problem which forms a minimal pair in the LK degrees; this is sharp in terms of the jump, as it is known that there are sets computable from which form a minimal pair in the LK degrees. We also show that the structure of LK degrees below the LK degree of the halting problem is not elementarily equivalent to the or structures of LK degrees. The proofs introduce a new technique of permitting below a set that is not K-trivial, which is likely to have wider applications.  相似文献   

18.
It is shown that every locally countable upper semi-lattice of cardinality the continuum can be embedded into the Turing degrees, assuming Martin’s Axiom.  相似文献   

19.
20.
Consider the countable semilattice T consisting of the recursivelyenumerable Turing degrees. Although T is known to be structurallyrich, a major source of frustration is that no specific, naturaldegrees in T have been discovered, except the bottom and topdegrees, 0 and 0'. In order to overcome this difficulty, weembed T into a larger degree structure which is better behaved.Namely, consider the countable distributive lattice w consistingof the weak degrees (also known as Muchnik degrees) of massproblems associated with non-empty 01 subsets of 2. It is knownthat w contains a bottom degree 0 and a top degree 1 and isstructurally rich. Moreover, w contains many specific, naturaldegrees other than 0 and 1. In particular, we show that in wone has 0 < d < r1 < f(r2, 1) < 1. Here, d is theweak degree of the diagonally non-recursive functions, and rnis the weak degree of the n-random reals. It is known that r1can be characterized as the maximum weak degree of a 01 subsetof 2 of positive measure. We now show thatf(r2, 1) can be characterizedas the maximum weak degree of a 01 subset of 2, the Turing upwardclosure of which is of positive measure. We exhibit a naturalembedding of T into w which is one-to-one, preserves the semilatticestructure of T, carries 0 to 0, and carries 0' to 1. IdentifyingT with its image in w, we show that all of the degrees in Texcept 0 and 1 are incomparable with the specific degrees d,r1, andf(r2, 1) in w.  相似文献   

设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号