首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
相似文献
 共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 15 毫秒
1.
We show that large fragments of MM, e. g. the tree property and stationary reflection, are preserved by strongly (ω1 + 1)‐game‐closed forcings. PFA can be destroyed by a strongly (ω1 + 1)‐game‐closed forcing but not by an ω2‐closed. (© 2004 WILEY‐VCH Verlag GmbH & Co. KGaA, Weinheim)  相似文献   

2.
We study game formulas the truth of which is determined by a semantical game of uncountable length. The main theme is the study of principles stating reflection of these formulas in various admissible sets. This investigation leads to two weak forms of strict-II11 reflection (or ∑1-compactness). We show that admissible sets such as H2) and Lω2 which fail to have strict-II11 reflection, may or may not, depending on set-theoretic hypotheses satisfy one or both of these weaker forms. Mathematics Subject Classification : 03C70, 03C75.  相似文献   

3.
Z. Balogh has shown that all normal, locally compact, screenable spaces are paracompact; it is known that the countably paracompact analogue of this theorem holds assuming V = L; in this paper we show that it also holds assuming Axiom R + MAω1, both of which follow from Martin's Maximum or PFA+(1), strengthenings of the Proper Forcing Axiom.  相似文献   

4.
We show that L(?) absoluteness for semi‐proper forcings is equiconsistent with the existence of a remarkable cardinal, and hence by [6] with L(?) absoluteness for proper forcings. By [7], L(?) absoluteness for stationary set preserving forcings gives an inner model with a strong cardinal. By [3], the Bounded Semi‐Proper Forcing Axiom (BSPFA) is equiconsistent with the Bounded Proper Forcing Axiom (BPFA), which in turn is equiconsistent with a reflecting cardinal. We show that Bounded Martin's Maximum (BMM) is much stronger than BSPFA in that if BMM holds, then for every XV , X# exists. (© 2004 WILEY‐VCH Verlag GmbH & Co. KGaA, Weinheim)  相似文献   

5.
The canonical function game is a game of length ω 1 introduced by W. Hugh Woodin which falls inside a class of games known as Neeman games. Using large cardinals, we show that it is possible to force that the game is not determined. We also discuss the relationship between this result and Σ2 2 absoluteness, cardinality spectra and Π2 maximality for H(ω 2) relative to the Continuum Hypothesis.  相似文献   

6.
We prove a local normal form theorem of the Gaifman type for the infinitary logic Lω( Q u)ω whose formulas involve arbitrary unary quantifiers but finite quantifier rank. We use a local Ehrenfeucht‐Fraïssé type game similar to the one in [9]. A consequence is that every sentence of Lω( Q u)ω of quantifier rank n is equivalent to an infinite Boolean combination of sentences of the form (?iy)ψ(y), where ψ(y) has counting quantifiers restricted to the (2n–1 – 1)‐neighborhood of y. (© 2005 WILEY‐VCH Verlag GmbH & Co. KGaA, Weinheim)  相似文献   

7.
《代数通讯》2013,41(8):2809-2825
Let k be a field and An(ω) be the Taft's n2-dimensional Hopf algebra. When n is odd, the Drinfeld quantum double D(An(ω)) of An(ω) is a ribbon Hopf algebra. In the previous articles, we constructed an n4-dimensional Hopf algebra Hn(p, q) which is isomorphic to D(An(ω)) if p ≠ 0 and q = ω?1 , and studied the irreducible representations of Hn(1, q) and the finite dimensional representations of H3(1, q). In this article, we examine the finite-dimensional representations of Hn(l q), equivalently, of D(An(ω)) for any n ≥ 2. We investigate the indecomposable left Hn(1, q)-module, and describe the structures and properties of all indecomposable modules and classify them when k is algebraically closed. We also give all almost split sequences in mod Hn(1, q), and the Auslander-Reiten-quiver of Hn(1 q).  相似文献   

8.
We first note that Gentzen's proof-reduction for his consistency proof of PA can be directly interpreted as moves of Kirby-Paris' Hydra Game, which implies a direct independence proof of the game (Section 1 and Appendix). Buchholz's Hydra Game for labeled hydras is known to be much stronger than PA. However, we show that the one-dimensional version of Buchholz's Game can be exactly identified to Kirby-Paris' Game (which is two-dimensional but without labels), by a simple and natural interpretation (Section 2). Jervell proposed another type of a combinatorial game, by abstracting Gentzen's proof-reductions and showed that his game is independent of PA. We show (Section 3) that this Jervell's game is actually much stronger than PA, by showing that the critical ordinal of Jervell's game is φω (0) (while that of PA or of Kirby-Paris' Game is φ1 (0) = ?0) in the Veblen hierarchy of ordinals.  相似文献   

9.
This is a contribution to the study of the Muchnik and Medvedev lattices of non‐empty Π01 subsets of 2ω. In both these lattices, any non‐minimum element can be split, i. e. it is the non‐trivial join of two other elements. In fact, in the Medvedev case, ifP > M Q, then P can be split above Q. Both of these facts are then generalised to the embedding of arbitrary finite distributive lattices. A consequence of this is that both lattices have decidible ?‐theories.  相似文献   

10.
We consider the theory Thprin of Boolean algebras with a principal ideal, the theory Thmax of Boolean algebras with a maximal ideal, the theory Thac of atomic Boolean algebras with an ideal where the supremum of the ideal exists, and the theory Thsa of atomless Boolean algebras with an ideal where the supremum of the ideal exists. First, we find elementary invariants for Thprin and Thsa. If T is a theory in a first order language and α is a linear order with least element, then we let Sentalg(T) be the Lindenbaum-Tarski algebra with respect to T, and we let intalg(α) be the interval algebra of α. Using rank diagrams, we show that Sentalg(Thprin) ? intalg(ω4), Sentalg(Thmax) ? intalg(ω3) ? Sentalg(Thac), and Sentalg(Thsa) ? intalg(ω2 + ω2). For Thmax and Thac we use Ershov's elementary invariants of these theories. We also show that the algebra of formulas of the theory Tx of Boolean algebras with finitely many ideals is atomic.  相似文献   

11.
We show that there is a model of ZF in which the Borel hierarchy on the reals has length ω2. This implies that ω1 has countable cofinality, so the axiom of choice fails very badly in our model. A similar argument produces models of ZF in which the Borel hierarchy has exactly λ + 1 levels for any given limit ordinal λ less than ω2. We also show that assuming a large cardinal hypothesis there are models of ZF in which the Borel hierarchy is arbitrarily long. (© 2008 WILEY‐VCH Verlag GmbH & Co. KGaA, Weinheim)  相似文献   

12.
We will prove that some so‐called union theorems (see [2]) are equivalent in ZF0 to statements about the transitive closure of relations. The special case of “bounded” union theorems dealing with κ‐hereditary sets yields equivalents to statements about the transitive closure of κ‐narrow relations. The instance κ = ω1 (i. e., hereditarily countable sets) yields an equivalent to Howard‐Rubin's Form 172 (the transitive closure Tc(x) of every hereditarily countable set x is countable). In particular, the countable union theorem (Howard‐Rubin's Form 31) and, a fortiori, the axiom of countable choice imply Form 172.  相似文献   

13.
We consider two models V1, V2 of ZFC such that V1V2, the cofinality functions of V1 and of V2 coincide, V1 and V2 have that same hereditarily countable sets, and there is some uncountable set in V2 that is not covered by any set in V1 of the same cardinality. We show that under these assumptions there is an inner model of V2 with a measurable cardinal κ of Mitchell order κ++. This technical result allows us to show that changing cardinal characteristics without changing cofinalities or ω‐sequences (which was done for some characteristics in [13]) has consistency strength at least Mitchell order κ++. From this we get that the changing of cardinal characteristics without changing cardinals or ω‐sequences has consistency strength Mitchell order ω1, even in the case of characteristics that do not stem from a transitive relation. Hence the known forcing constructions for such a change have lowest possible consistency strength. We consider some stronger violations of covering which have appeared as intermediate steps in forcing constructions.  相似文献   

14.
We use a bivariate spline method to solve the time evolution Navier‐Stokes equations numerically. The bivariate splines we use in this article are in the spline space of smoothness r and degree 3r over triangulated quadrangulations. The stream function formulation for the Navier‐Stokes equations is employed. Galerkin's method is applied to discretize the space variables of the nonlinear fourth‐order equation, Crank‐Nicholson's method is applied to discretize the time variable, and Newton's iterative method is then used to solve the resulting nonlinear system. We show the existence and uniqueness of the weak solution in L2(0, T; H2(Ω)) ∩ L(0, T; H1(Ω)) of the 2D nonlinear fourth‐order problem and give an estimate of how fast the numerical solution converges to the weak solution. The C1 cubic splines are implemented in MATLAB for solving the Navier‐Stokes equations numerically. Our numerical experiments show that the method is effective and efficient. © 2003 Wiley Periodicals, Inc. Numer Methods Partial Differential Eq 19: 776–827, 2003.  相似文献   

15.
We prove that the Kleene schemes for primitive recursion relative to the μ‐operator, relativized to some nondeterministic objects, have the same power to express total functionals when interpreted over the partial continuous functionals and over the Kleene‐Kreisel continuous functionals. Relating the former interpretation to Niggl's ℳ︁ω we prove Nigg's conjecture that ℳ︁ω is strictly weaker than Plotkin's PCF + PA.  相似文献   

16.
We consider symmetric flows of a viscous compressible barotropic fluid with a free boundary, under a general mass force depending both on the Eulerian and Lagrangian co‐ordinates, with arbitrarily large initial data. For a general non‐monotone state function p, we prove uniform‐in‐time energy bound and the uniform bounds for the density ρ, together with the stabilization as t → ∞ of the kinetic and potential energies. We also obtain H1‐stabilization of the velocity v to zero provided that the second viscosity is zero. For either increasing or non‐decreasing p, we study the Lλ‐stabilization of ρ and the stabilization of the free boundary together with the corresponding ω‐limit set in the general case of non‐unique stationary solution possibly with zones of vacuum. In the case of increasing p and stationary densities ρS separated from zero, we establish the uniform‐in‐time H1‐bounds and the uniform stabilization for ρ and v. All these results are stated and mainly proved in the Eulerian co‐ordinates. They are supplemented with the corresponding stabilization results in the Lagrangian co‐ordinates in the case of ρS separated from zero. Copyright © 2005 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd.  相似文献   

17.
We show that the vorticity of a viscous flow in ?3 admits an atomic decomposition of the form ω(x, t) = ωk(xxk, t), with localized and oscillating building blocks ωk, if such a property is satisfied at the beginning of the evolution. We also study the long time behavior of an isolated coherent structure and the special behavior of flows with highly oscillating vorticities. (© 2004 WILEY‐VCH Verlag GmbH & Co. KGaA, Weinheim)  相似文献   

18.
Let S be a locally compact semigroup, let ω be a weight function on S, and let Ma (S, ω) be the weighted semigroup algebra of S. Let L0 (S;Ma (S, ω)) be the C*‐algebra of allMa (S, ω)‐measurable functions g on S such that g /ω vanishes at infinity. We introduce and study an Arens multiplication on L0 (S;Ma (S, ω))* under which Ma (S, ω) is a closed ideal. We show that the weighted measure algebra M (S, ω) plays an important role in the structure of L0 (S;Ma (S, ω))*. We then study Arens regularity of L0 (S;Ma (S, ω))* and ist relation with Arens regularity of Ma (S, ω), M (S, ω) and the discrete convolution algebra 1(S, ω). As the main result, we prove that L0 (S;Ma (S, ω))* is Arens regular if and only if S is finite, or S is discrete and Ω is zero cluster. (© 2008 WILEY‐VCH Verlag GmbH & Co. KGaA, Weinheim)  相似文献   

19.
We discuss the question of Ralf‐Dieter Schindler whether for infinite time Turing machines Pf = NPf can be true for any function f from the reals into ω1. We show that “almost everywhere” the answer is negative.  相似文献   

20.
We show that it is consistent that Martin's axiom holds, the continuum is large, and yet the dual distributivity number ℌ is κ1. This answers a question of Halbeisen.  相似文献   

设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号