首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
相似文献
 共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 156 毫秒
1.
Realistic Mathematics Education supports students’ formalization of their mathematical activity through guided reinvention. To operationalize “formalization” in a proof-oriented instructional context, I adapt Sjogren's (2010) claim that formal proof explicates (Carnap, 1950) informal proof. Explication means replacing unscientific or informal concepts with scientific ones. I use Carnap's criteria for successful explication – similarity, exactness, and fruitfulness – to demonstrate how the elements of mathematical theory – definitions, axioms, theorems, proofs – can each explicate their less formal correlates. This lens supports an express goal of the instructional project, which is to help students coordinate semantic (informal) and syntactic (formal) mathematical activity. I demonstrate the analytical value of the explication lens by applying it to examples of students’ mathematical activity drawn from a design experiment in undergraduate, neutral axiomatic geometry. I analyze the chains of meanings (Thompson, 2013) that emerged when formal elements were presented readymade alongside those emerging from guided reinvention.  相似文献   

2.
We introduce a family of rigid hyperbolic 3-manifolds of infinite volume with possibly infinitely many ends: the treelike manifolds. These manifolds generalize a family of constructive non compact surfaces – the equational surfaces – for which the homeomorphism problem is decidable. The proof of rigidity relies firstly on Thurston's theorem of compactness of the Teichmüller space of acylindrical compact 3-manifolds, and secondly, on Sullivan's rigidity theorem. To cite this article: O. Ly, C. R. Acad. Sci. Paris, Ser. I 337 (2003).  相似文献   

3.
In 2006, Norine conjectured that a graph is k-Pfaffian but not (k1)-Pfaffian if and only if k is a power of four [Norine, S., Drawing 4-Pfaffian graphs on the torus, Combinatorica (accepted for publication), http://www.math.princeton.edu/~snorin/papers.html.]. Recently, we presented a graph that is a counter-example to that conjecture [Miranda, A. A. A. and C. L. Lucchesi, Matching signatures and Pfaffian graphs, Technical report, Institute of Computing – University of Campinas – UNICAMP (2009). URL http://www.ic.unicamp.br/~reltech/2009/09-06.pdf]. In this article, we present an alternative proof that this graph is a counter-example to the conjecture. In fact, we present a graph that is not 4-Pfaffian and give a simple proof that it is 10-Pfaffian, using new methods.  相似文献   

4.
We consider the cubic nonlinear Schrödinger equation with a potential in one space dimension. Under the assumptions that the potential is generic, sufficiently localized, with no bound states, we obtain the long-time asymptotic behavior of small solutions. In particular, we prove that, as time goes to infinity, solutions exhibit nonlinear phase corrections that depend on the scattering matrix associated to the potential. The proof of our result is based on the use of the distorted Fourier transform – the so-called Weyl–Kodaira–Titchmarsh theory – a precise understanding of the “nonlinear spectral measure” associated to the equation, and nonlinear stationary phase arguments and multilinear estimates in this distorted setting.  相似文献   

5.
Recently [6] an existence as well as a uniqueness theorem for the discontinuous oblique derivative problem for nonlinear elliptic system of first order in the plane, see [12, 19, 23] was proved, based on some a priori estimate from [20]. This estimate, however, is deduced by reductio ad absurdum. Therefore the constants in this estimate are unknown so that the estimate cannot be used for numerical procedures, e.g. for approximating the solution of a nonlinear problem by solutions of related linear problems, see [24, 3, 4]. In this paper a direct proof of an a priori estimate is given using some variations of results from [14], see also [11], where the constants can explicitely be estimated. For related a priori estimates see [1 – 5, 8, 16, 17, 20, 21, 24 – 26]. A basic reference for the oblique derivative problem is [9].  相似文献   

6.
This Note is devoted to the justification of an asymptotic model for quasisteady three-dimensional spherical flames proposed by G. Joulin [7]. The paper [7] derives, by means of a three-scale matched asymptotic expansion, starting from the classical thermo-diffusive model with high activation energies, an integro-differential equation for the flame radius. In the derivation, it is essential for the Lewis number – i.e., the ratio between thermal and molecular diffusion – to be strictly less than unity. In this Note, we give the main ideas of a rigorous proof of the validity of this model, under the additional restriction that the Lewis number is close to 1. To cite this article: C. Lederman et al., C. R. Acad. Sci. Paris, Ser. I 334 (2002) 569–574.  相似文献   

7.
The space of broken hyperbolic structures generalizes the usual Teichmüller space of a punctured surface, and the space of projectivized broken measured foliations – or, equivalently, the space of projectivized affine foliations of a punctured surface – likewise generalizes the space of projectivized measured foliations. Just as projectivized measured foliations provide Thurston's boundary for Teichmüller space, so too do projectivized broken measured foliations provide a boundary for the space of broken hyperbolic structures. In this paper, we naturally extend the Weil–Petersson Kähler two-form to a corresponding two-form on the space of broken hyperbolic structures as well as Thurston's symplectic form to a corresponding two-form on the space of broken measured foliations, and we show that the former limits in an appropriate sense to the latter. The proof in sketch follows earlier work of the authors for measured foliations and depends upon techniques from decorated Teichmüller theory, which is also applied here to a further study of broken hyperbolic structures.  相似文献   

8.
We investigate Hamilton Jacobi Isaacs equations associated to a two-players zero-sum differential game with incomplete information. The first player has complete information on the initial state of the game while the second player has only information of a – possibly uncountable – probabilistic nature: he knows a probability measure on the initial state. Such differential games with finite type incomplete information can be viewed as a generalization of the famous Aumann–Maschler theory for repeated games. The main goal and novelty of the present work consists in obtaining and investigating a Hamilton Jacobi Isaacs Equation satisfied by the upper and the lower values of the game. Since we obtain a uniqueness result for such Hamilton Jacobi equation, as a byproduct, this gives an alternative proof of the existence of a value of the differential game (which has been already obtained in the literature by different technics). Since the Hamilton Jacobi equation is naturally stated in the space of probability measures, we use the Wasserstein distance and some tools of optimal transport theory.  相似文献   

9.
10.
This paper discusses the process of proving from a novel theoretical perspective, imported from cognitive psychology research. This perspective highlights the role of hypothetical thinking, mental representations and working memory capacity in proving, in particular the effortful mechanism of cognitive decoupling: problem solvers need to form in their working memory two closely related models of the problem situation – the so-called primary and secondary representations – and to keep the two models decoupled, that is, keep the first fixed while performing various transformations on the second, while constantly struggling to protect the primary representation from being “contaminated” by the secondary one. We first illustrate the framework by analyzing a common scenario of introducing complex numbers to college-level students. The main part of the paper consists of re-analyzing, from the perspective of cognitive decoupling, previously published data of students searching for a non-trivial proof of a theorem in geometry. We suggest alternative (or additional) explanations for some well-documented phenomena, such as the appearance of cycles in repeated proving attempts, and the use of multiple drawings.  相似文献   

11.
The inhomogeneous mean-field thermodynamic limit is constructed and evaluated for both the canonical thermodynamic functions and the states of systems of classical point particles with logarithmic interactions in two space dimensions. The results apply to various physical models of translation invariant plasmas, gravitating systems, as well as to planar fluid vortex motion. For attractive interactions a critical behavior occurs which can be classified as an extreme case of a second-order phase transition. To include in particular attractive interactions a new inequality for configurational integrals is derived from the arithmetic-geometric mean inequality. The method developed in this paper is easily seen to apply as well to systems with fairly general interactions in all space dimensions. In addition, it also provides us with a new proof of the Trudinger-Moser inequality known from differential geometry – in its sharp form.  相似文献   

12.
Graham and Pollak [2] proved that n – 1 is the minimum number of edge-disjoint complete bipartite subgraphs into which the edges of Kn decompose. Tverberg [6], using a linear algebraic technique, was the first to give a simple proof of this result. We apply Tverberg's technique to obtain results for two related decomposition problems, in which we wish to partition the arcs/edges of complete digraphs/multigraphs into a minimum number of arc/edge-disjoint complete bipartite subgraphs of appropriate natures. We obtain exact results for the digraph problem, which was posed by Lundgren and Maybee [4]. We also obtain exact results for the decomposition of complete multigraphs with exactly two edges connecting every pair of distinct vertices.  相似文献   

13.
History and research on proof by contradiction suggests proof by contradiction is difficult for students in a number of ways. Students’ comprehension of already-written proofs by contradiction is one such aspect that has received relatively little attention. Applying the cognitive lens of Action-Process-Object-Schema (APOS) Theory to proof by contradiction, we constructed and tested a cognitive model that describes how a student might construct the concept ‘proof by contradiction’ in an introduction to proof course. Data for this study was collected from students in a series of five teaching interventions focused on proof by contradiction. This paper will report on two participants as case studies to illustrate that our cognitive trajectory for proof by contradiction is a useful model for describing how students may come to understand the proof method.  相似文献   

14.
Combinatorics is an area of mathematics with accessible, rich problems and applications in a variety of fields. Combinatorial proof is an important topic within combinatorics that has received relatively little attention within the mathematics education community, and there is much to investigate about how students reason about and engage with combinatorial proof. In this paper, we use Harel and Sowder’s (1998) proof schemes to investigate ways that students may characterize combinatorial proofs as different from other types of proof. We gave five upper-division mathematics students combinatorial-proof tasks and asked them to reflect on their activity and combinatorial proof more generally. We found that the students used several of Harel and Sowder’s proof schemes to characterize combinatorial proof, and we discuss whether and how other proof schemes may emerge for students engaging in combinatorial proof. We conclude by discussing implications and avenues for future research.  相似文献   

15.
Mathematicians and mathematics educators agree that proof is an important tool in mathematics, yet too often undergraduate students see proof as a superficial part of the discipline. While proof is often used by mathematicians to justify that a theorem is true, many times proof is used for another purpose entirely such as to explain why a particular statement is true or to show mathematics students a particular proof technique. This paper reports on a study that used a form of inquiry-based learning (IBL) in an introduction to proof course and measured the beliefs of students in this course about the different functions of proof in mathematics as compared to students in a non-IBL course. It was found that undergraduate students in an introduction to proof course had a more robust understanding of the functions of proof than previous studies would suggest. Additionally, students in the course taught using inquiry pedagogy were more likely to appreciate the communication, intellectual challenge, and providing autonomy functions of proof. It is hypothesized that these results are a response to the pedagogy of the course and the types of student activity that were emphasized.  相似文献   

16.
17.
Proof and reasoning are central to learning mathematics with understanding. Yet proof is seen as challenging to teach and to learn. In a capstone course for preservice teachers, we developed instructional modules that guided prospective secondary mathematics teachers (PSTs) through a cycle of learning about the logical aspects of proof, then planning and implementing lessons in secondary classrooms that integrate these aspects with traditional mathematics curriculum in the United States. In this paper we highlight our framework on mathematical knowledge for teaching proof and focus on some of the logical aspects of proof that are seen as particularly challenging (four proof themes). We analyze 60 lesson plans, video recordings of a subset of 13 enacted lessons, and the PSTs’ self- reported data to shed light on how the PSTs planned and enacted lessons that integrate these proof themes. The results provide insights into successes and challenges the PSTs encountered in this process and illustrate potential pathways for preparing PSTs to enact reasoning and proof in secondary classrooms. We also highlight the design principles for supporting the development of PSTs’ mathematical knowledge for teaching proof.  相似文献   

18.
In this paper, we propose an enriched and extended application of Harel and Sowder’s proof schemes taxonomy that can be used as a diagnostic tool for characterizing secondary students’ emergent learning of proof and proving. We illustrate this application in the analysis of data collected from 85 Year 9 (age 14–15) secondary students. We capture these students’ first encounters with proof and proving in an educational context (mixed ability, state schools in Greece) where mathematical proof is explicitly present in algebra and geometry lessons and where proving skills are typically expected, and rewarded, in key national examinations. We analyze student written responses to six questions, soon after the students had been introduced to proof and we identify evidence of six of the seven proof schemes proposed by Harel and Sowder as well as a further eight combinations of the six. We observed these combinations often within the response of the same student and to the same item. Here, we illustrate the eight combinations and we claim that a dynamic use of the proof schemes taxonomy that encompasses sole and combined proof schemes is a potent theoretical and pedagogical tool for mapping students’ multi-faceted and evolving competence in, and appreciation for, proof and proving.  相似文献   

19.
In the study reported here, we investigate the skills needed to validate a proof in real analysis, i.e., to determine whether a proof is valid. We first argue that when one is validating a proof, it is not sufficient to make certain that each statement in the argument is true. One must also check that there is good reason to believe that each statement follows from the preceding statements or from other accepted knowledge, i.e., that there is a valid warrant for making that statement in the context of this argument. We then report an exploratory study in which we investigated the behavior of 13 undergraduates when they were asked to determine whether or not a particular flawed mathematical argument is a valid mathematical proof. The last line of this purported proof was true, but did not follow legitimately from the earlier assertions in the proof. Our findings were that only six of these undergraduates recognized that this argument was invalid and only two did so for legitimate mathematical reasons. On a more positive note, when asked to consider whether the last line of the proof followed from previous assertions, a total of 10 students concluded that the statement did not and rejected the proof as invalid.  相似文献   

20.
We estimate the derivation lengths of functionals in G?del's system of primitive recursive functionals of finite type by a purely recursion-theoretic analysis of Schütte's 1977 exposition of Howard's weak normalization proof for . By using collapsing techniques from Pohlers' local predicativity approach to proof theory and based on the Buchholz-Cichon and Weiermann 1994 approach to subrecursive hierarchies we define a collapsing f unction so that for (closed) terms of G?del's we have: If reduces to then By one uniform proof we obtain as corollaries: A derivation lengths classification for functionals in , hence new proof of strongly uniform termination of . A new proof of the Kreisel's classific ation of the number-theoretic functions which can be defined in , hence a classification of the provably total functions of Peano Arithmetic. A new proof of Tait's results on weak normalization for . A new proof of Troelstra's result on strong normalization for . Additionally, a slow growing analysis of G?del's is obtained via Girard's hierarchy comparison theorem. This analyis yields a contribution to two open pro blems posed by Girard in part two of his book on proof theory. For the sake of completeness we also mention the Howard Schütte bound on derivation lengths for the simple typed -calculus. Received August 4, 1995  相似文献   

设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号