首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
相似文献
 共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 15 毫秒
1.
We characterize the sets of all Π2 and all $\mathcal {B}(\Sigma _{1})We characterize the sets of all Π2 and all $\mathcal {B}(\Sigma _{1})$ (= Boolean combinations of Σ1) theorems of IΠ?1 in terms of restricted exponentiation, and use these characterizations to prove that both sets are not deductively equivalent. We also discuss how these results generalize to n > 0. As an application, we prove that a conservation theorem of Beklemishev stating that IΠ?n + 1 is conservative over IΣ?n with respect to $\mathcal {B}(\Sigma _{n+1})$ sentences cannot be extended to Πn + 2 sentences. © 2011 WILEY‐VCH Verlag GmbH & Co. KGaA, Weinheim  相似文献   

2.
We introduce the notion of distinguished tree relation and give applications. We prove in ZFC an old conjecture of A.V. Ostrovsky about the image of a Borel space under a compact covering mapping. We also prove that if ?ξ+1L is countable then any compact covering mapping from a Δ11 space onto a Σ01+ξ+2 or Π01+ξ+2 space is inductively perfect. The converse of last statement is shown. To cite this article: G. Debs, J. Saint Raymond, C. R. Acad. Sci. Paris, Ser. I 336 (2003).  相似文献   

3.
We estimate the algorithmic complexity of the index set of some natural classes of computable models: finite computable models (Σ 2 0 -complete), computable models with ω-categorical theories (Δ ω 0 -complex Π ω+2 0 -set), prime models (Δ ω 0 -complex Π ω+2 0 -set), models with ω 1-categorical theories (Δ ω 0 -complex Σ ω+1 0 -set. We obtain a universal lower bound for the model-theoretic properties preserved by Marker’s extensions (Δ ω 0 .  相似文献   

4.
We construct an absolute retract X of arbitrarily high Borel complexity such that the countable power X ω is not universal for the Borelian class A 1 of sigma-compact spaces, and the product X ω x ∑, where ∑ is the radial interior of the Hilbert cube, is not universal for the Borelian class A 2 of absolute G δσ-spaces.  相似文献   

5.
Let R=GR(4,m) be the Galois ring of cardinality 4m and let T be the Teichmüller system of R. For every map λ of T into { -1,+1} and for every permutation Π of T, we define a map φ λ Π of Rinto { -1,+1} as follows: if xR and if x=a+2b is the 2-adic representation of x with xT and bT, then φ λ Π (x)=λ(a)+2Tr(Π(a)b), where Tr is the trace function of R . For i=1 or i=-1, define D i as the set of x in R such thatφ λ Π =i. We prove the following results: 1) D i is a Hadamard difference set of (R,+). 2) If φ is the Gray map of R into ${\mathbb{F}}_2^{2m}$ , then (D i) is a difference set of ${\mathbb{F}}_2^{2m}$ . 3) The set of D i and the set of φ(D i) obtained for all maps λ and Π, both are one-to-one image of the set of binary Maiorana-McFarland difference sets in a simple way. We also prove that special multiplicative subgroups of R are difference sets of kind D i in the additive group of R. Examples are given by means of morphisms and norm in R.  相似文献   

6.
In this paper we will state and prove some comparative theorems concerning PRA and IΣ1. We shall provide a characterization of IΣ1 in terms of PRA and iterations of a class of functions. In particular, we prove that for this class of functions the difference between IΣ1 and PRA is exactly that, where PRA is closed under iterations of these functions, IΣ1 is moreover provably closed under iteration. We will formulate a sufficient condition for a model of PRA to be a model of IΣ1. This condition is used to give a model-theoretic proof of Parsons’ theorem, that is, IΣ1 is Π2-conservative over PRA. We shall also give a purely syntactical proof of Parsons’ theorem. Finally, we show that IΣ1 proves the consistency of PRA on a definable IΣ1-cut. This implies that proofs in IΣ1 can have non-elementary speed up over proofs in PRA.  相似文献   

7.
In the case of a multinomial distribution Π1(1-Π1)+Π2(1-Π2)+…+ Πk(1-Πk) is at times referred to as Gini's index of diversity. In this paper, we present the distributional properties of the statistic
, based on samples of size n for a homogeneous multinomial distribution. For 2≤n≤ 12 and 2≤k≤12, we give a short table of the pdf, cdf, and the moments of D. For large values of n, we mention some results for the asymptotic distribution of D for the general multinomial distribution.  相似文献   

8.
Abstract. Let Ω and Π be two simply connected domains in the complex plane C which are not equal to the whole plane C and let λ Ω and λ Π denote the densities of the Poincare metric in Ω and Π , respectively. For f: Ω → Π analytic in Ω , inequalities of the type $$\frac{{|f^{(n)} (z)|}}{{n!}} \leqslant M_n (z,\Omega ,\Pi )\frac{{(\lambda _\Omega (z))^n }}{{\lambda _\Pi (f(z))}},z \in \Omega$$ are considered where M n (z,Ω, Π) does not depend on f and represents the smallest value possible at this place. We prove that $$M_n (z,\Delta ,\Pi ) = (1 + |z|)^{n - 1}$$ if Δ is the unit disk and Π is a convex domain. This generalizes a result of St. Ruscheweyh. Furthermore, we show that $$C_n (\Omega ,\Pi ) = sup\left\{ {M_n (z,\Omega ,\Pi )|z \in \Omega } \right\} \leqslant 4^{n - 1}$$ holds for arbitrary simply connected domains whereas the inequality 2 n-1 ≤ C n (Ω,Π) is proved only under some technical restrictions upon Ω and Π .  相似文献   

9.
We prove that determinacy for all Boolean combinations of \({F_{\sigma \delta }}\) (Π 3 0 ) sets implies the consistency of second-order arithmetic and more. Indeed, it is equivalent to the statement saying that for every set X and every number n, there exists a β-model of Π n 1 -comprehension containing X. We prove this result by providing a careful level-by-level analysis of determinacy at the finite level of the difference hierarchy on \({F_{\sigma \delta }}\) (Π 3 0 ) sets in terms of both reverse mathematics, complexity and consistency strength. We show that, for n ≥ 1, determinacy for sets at the nth level in this difference hierarchy lies strictly between (in the reverse mathematical sense of logical implication) the existence of β-models of Π n+2 1 -comprehension containing any given set X, and the existence of β-models of Δ n+2 1 -comprehension containing any given set X. Thus the nth of these determinacy axioms lies strictly between Π n+2 1 -comprehension and Δ n+2 1 -comprehension in terms of consistency strength. The major new technical result on which these proof theoretic ones are based is a complexity theoretic one. The nth determinacy axiom implies closure under the operation taking a set X to the least Σ n+1 admissible containing X (for n = 1; this is due to Welch [9]).  相似文献   

10.
Let X be a vector field in a compact n-manifold M, n?2. Given ΣM we say that qM satisfies (P)Σ if the closure of the positive orbit of X through q does not intersect Σ, but, however, there is an open interval I with q as a boundary point such that every positive orbit through I intersects Σ. Among those q having saddle-type hyperbolic omega-limit set ω(q) the ones with ω(q) being a closed orbit satisfy (P)Σ for some closed subset Σ. The converse is true for n=2 but not for n?4. Here we prove the converse for n=3. Moreover, we prove for n=3 that if ω(q) is a singular-hyperbolic set [C. Morales, M. Pacifico, E. Pujals, On C1 robust singular transitive sets for three-dimensional flows, C. R. Acad. Sci. Paris Sér. I 26 (1998) 81-86], [C. Morales, M. Pacifico, E. Pujals, Robust transitive singular sets for 3-flows are partially hyperbolic attractors or repellers, Ann. of Math. (2) 160 (2) (2004) 375-432], then ω(q) is a closed orbit if and only if q satisfies (P)Σ for some Σ closed. This result improves [S. Bautista, Sobre conjuntos hiperbólicos-singulares (On singular-hyperbolic sets), thesis Uiversidade Federal do Rio de Janeiro, 2005 (in Portuguese)] and [C. Morales, M. Pacifico, Mixing attractors for 3-flows, Nonlinearity 14 (2001) 359-378].  相似文献   

11.
The canonical function game is a game of length ω 1 introduced by W. Hugh Woodin which falls inside a class of games known as Neeman games. Using large cardinals, we show that it is possible to force that the game is not determined. We also discuss the relationship between this result and Σ2 2 absoluteness, cardinality spectra and Π2 maximality for H(ω 2) relative to the Continuum Hypothesis.  相似文献   

12.
In this paper, we show that, for each p 〉 1, there are continuum many Borel equivalence relations between Rω/l1 and Rω/p ordered by ≤B which are pairwise Borel incomparable.  相似文献   

13.
Theorem. There is a countable admissible set, Ol, with ordinal ωCK1 such that if S is Sacks generic over Ol then ω1S > ωCK1 and S is a nonminimal upper bound for the hyperdegrees in Ol. (The same holds over Ol for any upper bound produced by any forcing which can be construed so that the forcing relation for Σ1 formulas is Σ1.) A notion of forcing, the “delayed collapse” of ωCK1, is defined. The construction hinges upon the symmetries inherent in how this forcing interacts with Σ1 formulas. It also uses Steel trees to make a certain part of the generic object Σ1 over the final inner model, Ol, and, indeed, over many generic extensions of Ol.  相似文献   

14.
In this paper, we study the structure of Turing degrees below 0′ in the theory that is a fragment of Peano arithmetic without Σ1 induction, with special focus on proper d-r.e. degrees and non-r.e. degrees. We prove:
  1. P ? + BΣ1 + Exp ? There is a proper d-r.e. degree.
  2. P ? +BΣ1+ Exp ? IΣ1 ? There is a proper d-r.e. degree below 0′.
  3. P ? + BΣ1 + Exp ? There is a non-r.e. degree below 0′.
  相似文献   

15.
Questions concerning the structure of Borel sets were raised in special cases by Luzin, Aleksandrov, and Uryson as the problems of distinguishing the sets with certain homogeneous properties in Borel classes and determining the number of such pairwise nonhomemorphic sets. The universal homogeneity, i.e., the property to contain an everywhere closed copy of any Borel set of the same or smaller class, was considered by L.V. Keldysh. She called the sets of classes Π α 0 , α > 2, of first category in themselves that possess this homogeneity property canonical and proved their uniqueness. Thus she revealed the central role of the universality property when describing homeomorphic Borel sets. These investigations led her to the problem of universality of Borel sets and to the problem of finding conditions under which there exists an open map between Borel sets. In this paper, such conditions are presented and similar questions are considered for closed, compact-covering, harmonious, and other stable maps.  相似文献   

16.
Woodin has demonstrated that, in the presence of large cardinals, there is a single model of ZFC which is maximal for Π2-sentences over the structure (H(ω 2), ∈, NS ω1), in the sense that its (H(ω 2), ∈, NS ω1) satisfies every Π2-sentence σ for which (H(ω 2), ∈, NS ω1) ? σ can be forced by set-forcing. In this paper we answer a question of Woodin by showing that there are two Π2-sentences over the structure (H(ω 2), ∈, ω 1) which can each be forced to hold along with the continuum hypothesis, but whose conjunction implies $ {2^{{{\aleph_0}}}}={2^{{{\aleph_1}}}} $ . In the process we establish that there are two preservation theorems for not introducing new real numbers by a countable support iterated forcing which cannot be subsumed into a single preservation theorem.  相似文献   

17.
We prove that the Katětov order on Borel ideals (1) contains a copy of \(\mathcal {P}(\omega )/\mathbf {Fin}\), consequently it has increasing and decreasing chains of lenght ??; (2) the sequence F i n α (α < ω 1) is a strictly increasing chain; and (3) in the Cohen model, Katětov order does not contain any increasing nor decreasing chain of length ??, answering a question of Hru?ák (2011).  相似文献   

18.
Let X be a weakly complete space i.e. X a complex space endowed with a Ck-smooth, k?0, plurisubharmonic exhaustion function. We give the notion of minimal kernelΣ1=Σ1(X) of X by the following property: xΣ1 if no continuous plurisubharmonic exhaustion function is strictly plurisubharmonic near x. The study of the geometric properties of the minimal kernels is the aim of present paper. After stating that the minimal kernel Σ1 of a weakly complete space can be defined by a single plurisubharmonic exhaustion function ?, called minimal, using the characterization in terms of Bremermann envelopes, we prove the following, crucial, result: if X is a weakly complete manifold and ? a minimal function for X, the nonempty level sets Σc1=Σ1∩{?=c} have the local maximum property. In the last section we discuss the special case of weakly complete surfaces. We prove that if dimcX=2 and c is a regular value of a minimal function ? then the nonempty level sets Σc1=Σ1∩{?=c} are compact spaces foliated by holomorphic curves.  相似文献   

19.
Let k?ω, where ? is the set of all natural numbers. Ramsey's Theorem deals with colorings of the k-element subsets of ω. Our dual form deals with colorings of the k-element partitions of ω. Let (ω)k (respectively (ω)ω) be the set of all partitions of ω having exactly k (respectively infinitely many) blocks. Given X? (ω)ω let (X)k be the set of all Y? (ω)k such that Y is coarser than X. Dual Ramsey Theorem. If (ω)k = C0 ∪ … ∪ Ct?1 where each Ci is Borel then there exists X? (ω)ω such that (X)k ? Ci for some i <l. Dual Galvin-Prikry Theorem. Same as before with k replaced by ω. We also obtain dual forms of theorems of Ellentuck and Mathias. Our results also provide an infinitary generalization of the Graham-Rothschild “parameter set” theorem [Trans. Amer. Math. Soc.159 (1971), 257–292] and a new proof of the Halpern-Läuchli Theorem [Trans. Amer. Math. Soc.124 (1966), 360–367].  相似文献   

20.
设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号