首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
相似文献
 共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 15 毫秒
1.
John Harding 《Order》1993,10(3):283-294
If is a variety of orthomodular lattices generated by a set of orthomodular lattices having a finite uniform upper bound om the length of their chains, then the MacNeille completion of every algebra in again belongs to .The author gratefully acknowledges the support of NSERC.  相似文献   

2.
The class of orthomodular lattices which have only finitely many commutators is investigated. The following theorems are proved: contains the block-finite orthomodular lattices. Every irreducible element of is simple. Every element of is a direct product of a Boolean algebra and finitely many simple orthomodular lattices. The irreducible elements of which are modular, or are M-symmetric with at least one atom, have height two or less.  相似文献   

3.
John Harding 《Order》1991,8(1):93-103
The only known example of an orthomodular lattice (abbreviated: OML) whose MacNeille completion is not an OML has been noted independently by several authors, see Adams [1], and is based on a theorem of Ameniya and Araki [2]. This theorem states that for an inner product space V, if we consider the ortholattice ?(V,⊥) = {A \( \subseteq \) V: A = A ⊥⊥} where A is the set of elements orthogonal to A, then ?(V,⊥) is an OML if and only if V is complete. Taking the orthomodular lattice L of finite or confinite dimensional subspaces of an incomplete inner product space V, the ortholattice ?(V,⊥) is a MacNeille completion of L which is not orthomodular. This does not answer the longstanding question Can every OML be embedded into a complete OML? as L can be embedded into the complete OML ?(V,⊥), where V is the completion of the inner product space V. Although the power of the Ameniya-Araki theorem makes the preceding example elegant to present, the ability to picture the situation is lost. In this paper, I present a simpler method to construct OMLs whose Macneille completions are not orthomodular. No use is made of the Ameniya-Araki theorem. Instead, this method is based on a construction introduced by Kalmbach [7] in which the Boolean algebras generated by the chains of a lattice are glued together to form an OML. A simple method to complete these OMLs is also given. The final section of this paper briefly covers some elementary properties of the Kalmbach construction. I have included this section because I feel that this construction may be quite useful for many purposes and virtually no literature has been written on it.  相似文献   

4.
Hans Weber 《Order》1995,12(3):295-305
It is shown that the lattice of all exhaustive lattice uniformities on an orthomodular latticeL is isomorphic to the centre of a natural completion (of a quotient) ofL, and is thus a complete Boolean algebra. This is applied to prove a decomposition theorem for exhaustive modular functions on orthomodular lattices, which generalizes Traynor's decomposition theorem [14].  相似文献   

5.
6.
For any finitely based variety of orthomodular lattices, we determine the sizes of all equational bases that are both irredundant and self-dual.  相似文献   

7.
8.
In this paper we continue to investigate projectivity in orthomodular lattices. We prove the somewhat surprising result that no uncountable Boolean algebra is projective in the variety of orthomodular lattices. Received January 7, 1994; accepted in final form July 16, 1996.  相似文献   

9.
Projective geometry is formulated in the language of geometric algebra, a unified mathematical language based on Clifford algebra. This closes the gap between algebraic and synthetic approaches to projective geometry and facilitates connections with the rest of mathematics.This work was partially supported by NSF grant MSM-8645151.  相似文献   

10.
The design of linear algebra and geometry   总被引:2,自引:0,他引:2  
Conventional formulations of linear algebra do not do justice to the fundamental concepts of meet, join, and duality in projective geometry. This defect is corrected by introducing Clifford algebra into the foundations of linear algebra. There is a natural extension of linear transformations on a vector space to the associated Clifford algebra with a simple projective interpretation. This opens up new possibilities for coordinate-free computations in linear algebra. For example, the Jordan form for a linear transformation is shown to be equivalent to a canonical factorization of the unit pseudoscalar. This approach also reveals deep relations between the structure of the linear geometries, from projective to metrical, and the structure of Clifford algebras. This is apparent in a new relation between additive and multiplicative forms for intervals in the cross-ratio. Also, various factorizations of Clifford algebras into Clifford algebras of lower dimension are shown to have projective interpretations.As an important application with many uses in physics as well as in mathematics, the various representations of the conformal group in Clifford algebra are worked out in great detail. A new primitive generator of the conformal group is identified.  相似文献   

11.
12.
Relations between ideals and commutative group valued finitely additive functions on orth-omodular lattices are studied. Nontrivial examples of orthomodular lattices with all nontrivial quotients being Boolean are found.Dedicated to the memory of Alan Day.Presented by J. Sichler.  相似文献   

13.
14.
15.
16.
The main aim of this paper is the calculation of the dimension of certain atomic amalgams. These consist of finite Boolean algebras (blocks) pasted together in such a way that a pair of blocks intersects either trivially in the bounds, or the intersection consists of the bounds, an atom, and its complement.  相似文献   

17.
18.
This paper answers a question of H. P. Sankappanavar who asked whether the theory of orthomodular lattices is recursively (finitely) inseparable (question 9 in [10]). A very similar question was raised by Stanley Burris at the Oberwolfach meeting on Universal Algebra, July 15–21, 1979, and was later included in G. Kalmbach’s monograph [6] as the problem 42. Actually Burris asked which varieties of orthomodular lattices are finitely decidable. Although we are not able to give a full answer to Burris’ question we have a contribution to the problem.   Note here that each finitely generated variety of orthomodular lattices is semisimple arithmetical and therefore directly representable. Consequently each such a variety is finitely decidable. (For a generalization of this, i.e. a characterization of finitely generated congruence modular varieties that are finitely decidable see [5].) In section 3, we give an example of finitely decidable variety of orthomodular lattices that is not finitely generated. Received June 28, 1995; accepted in final form June 27, 1996.  相似文献   

19.
20.
It is well known that for a chain finite orthomodular lattice, all congruences are factor congruences, so any directly irreducible chain finite orthomodular lattice is simple. In this paper it is shown that the notions of directly irreducible and simple coincide in any variety generated by a set of orthomodular lattices that has a uniform finite upper bound on the lengths of their chains. The prototypical example of such a variety is any variety generated by a set ofn dimensional orthocomplemented projective geometries.Presented by B. Jónsson.Supported by a grant from NSERC.  相似文献   

设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号