首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
相似文献
 共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 15 毫秒
1.
In this work an investigation of the uncertainty principle and the complementarity principle is carried through. A study of the physical content of these principles and their representation in the conventional Hilbert space formulation of quantum mechanics forms a natural starting point for this analysis. Thereafter is presented more general axiomatic framework for quantum mechanics, namely, a probability function formulation of the theory. In this general framework two extra axioms are stated, reflecting the ideas of the uncertainty principle and the complementarity principle, respectively. The quantal features of these axioms are explicated. The sufficiency of the state system guarantees that the observables satisfying the uncertainty principle are unbounded and noncompatible. The complementarity principle implies a non-Boolean proposition structure for the theory. Moreover, nonconstant complementary observables are always noncompatible. The uncertainty principle and the complementarity principle, as formulated in this work, are mutually independent. Some order is thus brought into the confused discussion about the interrelations of these two important principles. A comparison of the present formulations of the uncertainty principle and the complementarity principle with the Jauch formulation of the superposition principle is also given. The mutual independence of the three fundamental principles of the quantum theory is hereby revealed.  相似文献   

2.
It is shown that in fairly general circumstances the event and observable frameworks for axiomatic quantum mechanics are equivalent.  相似文献   

3.
A new metric which we call the intrinsic metric is introduced on the states of the generalized logic of quantum mechanics. It is shown that every automorphism on is an isometry. A norm can be defined on the linear spanE of which reduces to the intrinsic metric on. IfX is the completion ofE then every automorphism, on has a unique extension to a linear isometry onX. A comparison is made between these results and those of Kroniff.  相似文献   

4.
Letp(A,,E) be the probability that a measurement of an observableA for the system in a state will lead to a value in a Borel setE. An experimental function is a function f from the set of all statesI into [0,1] for which there are an observableA and a Borel setE such thatf()=p(A, , E) for all I. A sequencef 1,f 2,... of experimental functions is said to be orthogonal if there is an experimental functiong such thatg+f 1+f 2+...=1, and it is said to be pairwise orthogonal iff i+f j 1 forij. It is shown that if we assume both notions to be equivalent then the setL of all experimental functions is an orthocomplemented partially ordered set with respect to the natural order of real functions with the complementationf=1–f, each observableA can be identified with anL-valued measure A, each state can be identified with a probability measurem onL and we havep(A,,E)=m oA(E). Thus we obtain the abstract setting of axiomatic quantum mechanics as a consequence of a single postulate.  相似文献   

5.
Observables are treated as-homomorphisms of the Borel sets of the real line into an orthomodular-latticeL. By means of corresponding spectral-resolutions operations meet and join are defined between observables which endow the set of all observables with a lattice structure in caseL is-continuous and which give rise to lattices of observables in caseL is chosen arbitrarily and the observables commute.  相似文献   

6.
The Euler-Lagrange equation derived from Schwinger's action principle (1951) has been shown by Kianget al. (1969) and Linet al. (1970) to lead to inconsistencies for quadratic lagrangians of the form $$\bar L(\dot q,q) = \tfrac{1}{2}\dot q^j g_{jk} (q)\dot q^k - V(q)$$ except in the Euclidean caseg jk =δ jk . This inadequacy is linked to Schwinger's specification that the variations of operators bec-numbers. We reformulate the action principle by introducing the concept of ‘proper’ Gauteaux variation of operators to find the most general class of admissible variation consistent with the postulated quantisation rules. This new action principle, applied to the LagrangianL, yields a quantum Euler equation consistent with the Hamilton-Heisenberg equations.  相似文献   

7.
8.
This contribution continues the series of papers [2, 4, 5, 12] treated by Ludwig and collaborators. It is based on the generalized frame given in [6]; there Ludwig has set up an infinite axiomatic scheme as extension of the finite system [4, 5]. The results of [12] are then proved for a locally finite case; they lead to an extended representation theorem.This paper was supported by the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft.  相似文献   

9.
We continue here the series of papers treated byLudwig in [1–5]. Using some results ofDähn in [6], we point out that each irreducible solution of the axiomatic scheme set up in [5] is represented by a system of positive-semi-definite operator pairs of a finite-dimensional Hilbert-space over the real, complex or quaternionic numbers.This paper is an abridged version of the author's thesis presented to the Marburg University and written under the direction of Prof.G. Ludwig.  相似文献   

10.
11.
喀兴林 《大学物理》2006,25(6):1-4,15
以对话的形式,介绍并评论了布洛欣采夫、狄拉克以及朗道和栗弗席茨关于状态叠加原理的不同表述.  相似文献   

12.
The consequences of an axiomatic formulation of physical probability fields established in a first paper [1] are investigated in case of a finite dimensional ensemble-space.It will be shown that the stated number of axioms can be diminuished essentially. Further the structure of an ortho-complemented orthomodular lattice for the decision effects (also often called properties or still more misunderstandingly propositions) and the orthoadditivity of the probability measures upon this lattice, both, can be essentially inferred from the axioms 3 and 4,only. This seems to give a better comprehension of the lattice structure defined by the decision effects.Particularly, it is pointed out that no assumption (axiom) concerning the commensurability of two decision effectsE 1 E 2 withE 1E 2 must be made but that this commensurability is a theorem of the theory.  相似文献   

13.
Starting from axioms as physical as possible [1, 2, 3] about effects and ensembles, we shall investigate further consequences.Concerning part I and II [4, 5] the axioms can be so formulated as to be surveyed more easily.Besides, it is possible to prove some important theorems more simply.New structures of the lattice of decision effects are pointed out, leading in two subsequent papers at last to the final aim, the structure of Hilbert-space.  相似文献   

14.
This contribution continues the series of papers on the same subject which has been treated byLudwig in [1–3]. Using the system of axioms as given in [3], we shall succeed in constructing an orthomodular lattice of linear operators on the real vector space generated by the physical decision effects. There results an isomorphism between the orthomodular lattice of all physical decision effects and the lattice to be constructed.  相似文献   

15.
There are four reasons why our present knowledge and understanding of quantum mechanics can be regarded as incomplete. (1) The principle of linear superposition has not been experimentally tested for position eigenstates of objects having more than about a thousand atoms. (2) There is no universally agreed upon explanation for the process of quantum measurement. (3) There is no universally agreed upon explanation for the observed fact that macroscopic objects are not found in superposition of position eigenstates. (4) Most importantly, the concept of time is classical and hence external to quantum mechanics: there should exist an equivalent reformulation of the theory which does not refer to an external classical time. In this paper we argue that such a reformulation is the limiting case of a nonlinear quantum theory, with the nonlinearity becoming important at the Planck mass scale. Such a nonlinearity can provide insights into the aforesaid problems. We use a physically motivated model for a nonlinear Schr?dinger equation to show that nonlinearity can help in understanding quantum measurement. We also show that while the principle of linear superposition holds to a very high accuracy for atomic systems, the lifetime of a quantum superposition becomes progressively smaller, as one goes from microscopic to macroscopic objects. This can explain the observed absence of position superpositions in macroscopic objects (lifetime is too small). It also suggests that ongoing laboratory experiments may be able to detect the finite superposition lifetime for mesoscopic objects in the near future.  相似文献   

16.
关洪 《大学物理》2007,26(1):7-9,12
讨论了量子力学中态叠加原理的意义,评论了它的不同表述和解说,并且以简单明了的语言来叙述这一原理.  相似文献   

17.
18.
The “weak-maximality” condition is proved to be equivalent to atomicity of the lattice of “propositions” (“decision effects”) in quantum axiomatics, satisfying certain simple conditions. In particular, it is shown that these conditions are fulfilled in Ludwig's axiomatic formulation of quantum mechanics. It is further proved that atomicity of the lattice of propositions follows from the condition of “strong maximality”. The maximality conditions have a clear physical interpretation. They are also fulfilled in the Hilbert space formulation of quantum mechanics. Since the atomicity property is used in theories based on Type I factors, the connection between atomicity and maximality seems of general interest. Useful theorems are proved.  相似文献   

19.
20.
It is shown that Møller matricesS ± and scattering matrixS in axiomatic field theory can be expressed through their adiabatic analogs. In particular, it is proved under certain conditions that \(S_ - = \mathop {s\lim }\limits_{\alpha \to 0} S_\alpha (0,\infty )W_\alpha \) whereW α is a trivial phase factor [i.e. a unitary operator of the form exp i / α ∝r(k)a + (k)a(k)dk]. Corresponding results in Hamiltonian approach are discussed.  相似文献   

设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号