首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
相似文献
 共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 734 毫秒
1.
2.
This paper presents an abstract study of completeness properties of non-classical logics with respect to matricial semantics. Given a class of reduced matrix models we define three completeness properties of increasing strength and characterize them in several useful ways. Some of these characterizations hold in absolute generality and others are for logics with generalized implication or disjunction connectives, as considered in the previous papers. Finally, we consider completeness with respect to matrices with a linear dense order and characterize it in terms of an extension property and a syntactical metarule. This is the final part of the investigation started and developed in the papers (Cintula and Noguera in Arch Math Logic 49(4):417–446, 2010; Arch Math Logic 53(3):353–372, 2016).  相似文献   

3.
We show that as long as the propositional constants t and f are not included in the language, any language-preserving extension of any important fragment of the relevance logics R and RMI can have only classical tautologies as theorems (this includes intuitionistic logic and its extensions). This property is not preserved, though, if either t or f is added to the language, or if the contraction axiom is deleted.  相似文献   

4.
Logics that have many truth values—more than just True and False—have been argued to be useful in the analysis of very many philosophical and linguistic puzzles (as well, sometimes, in various computational-oriented tasks). In this paper, which is a followup to (Hazen and Pelletier in K3, ?3, LP, RM3, A3, FDE, M: How to make many-valued logics work for you. Winning paper for the Canadian Schotch-Jennings Prize, one of the prizes of the Universal Logic competition in 2018; Notre Dame J Form Log 59, 2018), we will start with a particularly well-motivated four-valued logic that has been studied mainly in its propositional and first-order versions. And we will then investigate its second-order version. This four-valued logic has two natural three-valued extensions: what is called a “gap logic” (some formulas are neither True nor False), and what is called a “glut logic” (some formulas are both True and False). We mention various results about the second-order version of these logics as well. And we then follow our earlier papers, where we had added a specific conditional connective to the three valued logics, and now add that connective to the four-valued logic under consideration. We then show that, although this addition is “conservative” in the sense that no new theorems are generated in the four-valued logic unless they employ this new conditional in their statement, nevertheless the resulting second-order versions of these logics with and without the conditional are quite different in important ways. We close with a moral for logical investigations in this realm.  相似文献   

5.
Does there exist any equivalence between the notions of inconsistency and consequence in paraconsistent logics as is present in the classical two valued logic? This is the key issue of this paper. Starting with a language where negation (?{\neg}) is the only connective, two sets of axioms for consequence and inconsistency of paraconsistent logics are presented. During this study two points have come out. The first one is that the notion of inconsistency of paraconsistent logics turns out to be a formula-dependent notion and the second one is that the characterization (i.e. equivalence) appears to be pertinent to a class of paraconsistent logics which have double negation property.  相似文献   

6.
Wolter in [38] proved that the Craig interpolation property transfers to fusion of normal modal logics. It is well-known [21] that for such logics Craig interpolation corresponds to an algebraic property called superamalgamability. In this paper, we develop model-theoretic techniques at the level of first-order theories in order to obtain general combination results transferring quantifier-free interpolation to unions of theories over non-disjoint signatures. Such results, once applied to equational theories sharing a common Boolean reduct, can be used to prove that superamalgamability is modular also in the non-normal case. We also state that, in this non-normal context, superamalgamability corresponds to a strong form of interpolation that we call “comprehensive interpolation property” (which consequently transfers to fusions).  相似文献   

7.
In abstract algebraic logic, the general study of propositional non-classical logics has been traditionally based on the abstraction of the Lindenbaum-Tarski process. In this process one considers the Leibniz relation of indiscernible formulae. Such approach has resulted in a classification of logics partly based on generalizations of equivalence connectives: the Leibniz hierarchy. This paper performs an analogous abstract study of non-classical logics based on the kind of generalized implication connectives they possess. It yields a new classification of logics expanding Leibniz hierarchy: the hierarchy of implicational logics. In this framework the notion of implicational semilinear logic can be naturally introduced as a property of the implication, namely a logic L is an implicational semilinear logic iff it has an implication such that L is complete w.r.t. the matrices where the implication induces a linear order, a property which is typically satisfied by well-known systems of fuzzy logic. The hierarchy of implicational logics is then restricted to the semilinear case obtaining a classification of implicational semilinear logics that encompasses almost all the known examples of fuzzy logics and suggests new directions for research in the field.  相似文献   

8.
We continue the investigations initiated in the recent papers (Brown et al. in The modal logic of Bayesian belief revision, 2017; Gyenis in Standard Bayes logic is not finitely axiomatizable, 2018) where Bayes logics have been introduced to study the general laws of Bayesian belief revision. In Bayesian belief revision a Bayesian agent revises (updates) his prior belief by conditionalizing the prior on some evidence using the Bayes rule. In this paper we take the more general Jeffrey formula as a conditioning device and study the corresponding modal logics that we call Jeffrey logics, focusing mainly on the countable case. The containment relations among these modal logics are determined and it is shown that the logic of Bayes and Jeffrey updating are very close. It is shown that the modal logic of belief revision determined by probabilities on a finite or countably infinite set of elementary propositions is not finitely axiomatizable. The significance of this result is that it clearly indicates that axiomatic approaches to belief revision might be severely limited.  相似文献   

9.
We look into methods which make it possible to determine whether or not the modal logics under examination are residually finite w.r.t. admissible inference rules. A general condition is specified which states that modal logics over K4 are not residually finite w.r.t. admissibility. It is shown that all modal logics over K4 of width strictly more than 2 which have the co-covering property fail to be residually finite w.r.t. admissible inference rules; in particular, such are K4, GL, K4.1, K4.2, S4.1, S4.2, and GL.2. It is proved that all logics over S4 of width at most 2, which are not sublogics of three special table logics, possess the property of being residually finite w.r.t. admissibility. A number of open questions are set up.  相似文献   

10.
Formal systems of fuzzy logic and their fragments   总被引:1,自引:0,他引:1  
Formal systems of fuzzy logic (including the well-known Łukasiewicz and Gödel–Dummett infinite-valued logics) are well-established logical systems and respected members of the broad family of the so-called substructural logics closely related to the famous logic BCK. The study of fragments of logical systems is an important issue of research in any class of non-classical logics. Here we study the fragments of nine prominent fuzzy logics to all sublanguages containing implication. However, the results achieved in the paper for those nine logics are usually corollaries of theorems with much wider scope of applicability. In particular, we show how many of these fragments are really distinct and we find axiomatic systems for most of them. In fact, we construct strongly separable axiomatic systems for eight of our nine logics. We also fully answer the question for which of the studied fragments the corresponding class of algebras forms a variety. Finally, we solve the problem how to axiomatize predicate versions of logics without the lattice disjunction (an essential connective in the usual axiomatic system of fuzzy predicate logics).  相似文献   

11.
In Béziau (Log Log Philos 15:99–111, 2006) a logic \(\mathbf {Z}\) was defined with the help of the modal logic \(\mathbf {S5}\). In it, the negation operator is understood as meaning ‘it is not necessary that’. The strong soundness–completeness result for \(\mathbf {Z}\) with respect to a version of Kripke semantics was also given there. Following the formulation of \(\mathbf {Z}\) we can talk about \(\mathbf {Z}\)-like logics or Beziau-style logics if we consider other modal logics instead of \(\mathbf {S5}\)—such a possibility has been mentioned in [1]. The correspondence result between modal logics and respective Beziau-style logics has been generalised for the case of normal logics naturally leading to soundness–completeness results [see Marcos (Log Anal 48(189–192):279–300, 2005) and Mruczek-Nasieniewska and Nasieniewski (Bull Sect Log 34(4):229–248, 2005)]. In Mruczek-Nasieniewska and Nasieniewski (Bull Sect Log 37(3–4):185–196, 2008), (Bull Sect Log 38(3–4):189–203, 2009) some partial results for non-normal cases are given. In the present paper we try to give similar but more general correspondence results for the non-normal-worlds case. To achieve this aim we have to enrich original Beziau’s language with an additional negation operator understood as ‘it is necessary that not’.  相似文献   

12.
In Hájek et al. (J Symb Logic 65(2):669–682, 2000) the authors introduce the concept of supersound logic, proving that first-order Gödel logic enjoys this property, whilst first-order ?ukasiewicz and product logics do not; in Hájek and Shepherdson (Ann Pure Appl Logic 109(1–2):65–69, 2001) this result is improved showing that, among the logics given by continuous t-norms, Gödel logic is the only one that is supersound. In this paper we will generalize the previous results. Two conditions will be presented: the first one implies the supersoundness and the second one non-supersoundness. To develop these results we will use, between the other machineries, the techniques of completions of MTL-chains developed in Labuschagne and van Alten (Proceedings of the ninth international conference on intelligent technologies, 2008) and van Alten (2009). We list some of the main results. The first-order versions of MTL, SMTL, IMTL, WNM, NM, RDP are supersound; the first-order version of an axiomatic extension of BL is supersound if and only it is n-potent (i.e. it proves the formula \({\varphi^{n}\,\to\,\varphi^{n\,{+}\,1}}\) for some \({n\,\in\,\mathbb{N}^+}\)). Concerning the negative results, we have that the first-order versions of ΠMTL, WCMTL and of each non-n-potent axiomatic extension of BL are not supersound.  相似文献   

13.
Mirko Navara  Pavel Pták 《Order》1988,4(4):387-395
Following the definition of S. Gudder and J. Zerbe, we say that a logicL has the Radon-Nikodym property (or, in short,L is an RN logic) if the following condition holds: Ifs, t are states onL ands is absolutely continuous with respect tot, then there is a central observablex such that for allaL. We first consider general RN logics. We establish their basic properties and show that they are closed under the formation of epimorphisms and products. Then we take up the RN property for concrete logics. We first show that in many cases the concrete RN logics have to be fully compatible (= Boolean -algebras). In contrast to that, we show that there are concrete RN logics with an arbitrary degree of noncompatibility. This extends the result of Navara and Pták and answers in full the question posed by Gudder and Zerbe.  相似文献   

14.
Along the same line as that in Ono (Ann Pure Appl Logic 161:246–250, 2009), a proof-theoretic approach to Glivenko theorems is developed here for substructural predicate logics relative not only to classical predicate logic but also to arbitrary involutive substructural predicate logics over intuitionistic linear predicate logic without exponentials QFL e . It is shown that there exists the weakest logic over QFL e among substructural predicate logics for which the Glivenko theorem holds. Negative translations of substructural predicate logics are studied by using the same approach. First, a negative translation, called extended Kuroda translation is introduced. Then a translation result of an arbitrary involutive substructural predicate logics over QFL e is shown, and the existence of the weakest logic is proved among such logics for which the extended Kuroda translation works. They are obtained by a slight modification of the proof of the Glivenko theorem. Relations of our extended Kuroda translation with other standard negative translations will be discussed. Lastly, algebraic aspects of these results will be mentioned briefly. In this way, a clear and comprehensive understanding of Glivenko theorems and negative translations will be obtained from a substructural viewpoint.  相似文献   

15.
In this paper we introduce non-normal modal extensions of the sub-classical logics CLoN, CluN and CLaN, in the same way that S0.5 0 extends classical logic. The first modal system is both paraconsistent and paracomplete, while the second one is paraconsistent and the third is paracomplete. Despite being non-normal, these systems are sound and complete for a suitable Kripke semantics. We also show that these systems are appropriate for interpreting □ as “is provable in classical logic”. This allows us to recover the theorems of propositional classical logic within three sub-classical modal systems.  相似文献   

16.
Zolin  E. E. 《Mathematical Notes》2002,72(5-6):784-798
Hilbert systems L and sequential calculi [L ] for the versions of logics L= T,S4,B,S5, and Grz stated in a language with the single modal noncontingency operator A=A¬ A are constructed. It is proved that cut is not eliminable in the calculi [L ], but we can restrict ourselves to analytic cut preserving the subformula property. Thus the calculi [T ], [S4 ], [S5 ] ([Grz ], respectively) satisfy the (weak, respectively) subformula property; for [B 2 ], this question remains open. For the noncontingency logics in question, the Craig interpolation property is established.  相似文献   

17.
In this paper, we introduce the notion of dual Post’s negation and an infinite class of Dual Post’s finitely-valued logics which differ from Post’s ones with respect to the definitions of negation and the sets of designated truth values. We present adequate natural deduction systems for all Post’s k-valued (\(k\geqslant 3\)) logics as well as for all Dual Post’s k-valued logics.  相似文献   

18.
With any structural inference rule A/B, we associate the rule ${(A \lor p)/(B \lor p)}$ , providing that formulas A and B do not contain the variable p. We call the latter rule a join-extension ( ${\lor}$ -extension, for short) of the former. Obviously, for any intermediate logic with disjunction property, a ${\lor}$ -extension of any admissible rule is also admissible in this logic. We investigate intermediate logics, in which the ${\lor}$ -extension of each admissible rule is admissible. We prove that any structural finitary consequence operator (for intermediate logic) can be defined by a set of ${\lor}$ -extended rules if and only if it can be defined through a set of well-connected Heyting algebras of a corresponding quasivariety. As we exemplify, the latter condition is satisfied for a broad class of algebraizable logics.  相似文献   

19.
In this paper we present the proof-theoretical approach to p-adic valued conditional probabilistic logics. We introduce two such logics denoted by CPLZp and CPLQpfin. Each of these logics extends classical propositional logic with a list of binary (conditional probability) operators. Formulas are interpreted in Kripke-like models that are based on p-adic probability spaces. Axiomatic systems with infinitary rules of inference are given and proved to be sound and strongly complete. The decidability of the satisfiability problem for each logic is proved.  相似文献   

20.
Correspondence analysis is Kooi and Tamminga’s universal approach which generates in one go sound and complete natural deduction systems with independent inference rules for tabular extensions of many-valued functionally incomplete logics. Originally, this method was applied to Asenjo–Priest’s paraconsistent logic of paradox LP. As a result, one has natural deduction systems for all the logics obtainable from the basic three-valued connectives of LP (which is built in the \( \{\vee ,\wedge ,\lnot \} \)-language) by the addition of unary and binary connectives. Tamminga has also applied this technique to the paracomplete analogue of LP, strong Kleene logic \( \mathbf K_3 \). In this paper, we generalize these results for the negative fragments of LP and \( \mathbf K_3 \), respectively. Thus, the method of correspondence analysis works for the logics which have the same negations as LP or \( \mathbf K_3 \), but either have different conjunctions or disjunctions or even don’t have them as well at all. Besides, we show that correspondence analyses for the negative fragments of \( \mathbf K_3 \) and LP, respectively, are also suitable without any changes for the negative fragments of Heyting’s logic \( \mathbf G_3 \) and its dual \( \mathbf DG_3 \) (which have different interpretations of negation than \( \mathbf K_3 \) and LP).  相似文献   

设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号