首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
相似文献
 共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 15 毫秒
1.

The usual no-cloning theorem implies that two quantum states are identical or orthogonal if we allow a cloning to be on the two quantum states. Here, we investigate a relation between the no-cloning theorem and the projective measurement theory that the results of measurements are either + 1 or − 1. We introduce the Kochen-Specker (KS) theorem with the projective measurement theory. We result in the fact that the two quantum states under consideration cannot be orthogonal if we avoid the KS contradiction. Thus the no-cloning theorem implies that the two quantum states underconsideration are identical in that case. It turns out that the KS theorem with the projective measurement theory says a new version of the no-cloning theorem. Next, we investigate a relation between the no-cloning theorem and the measurement theory based on the truth values that the results of measurements are either + 1 or 0. We return to the usual no-cloning theorem that the two quantum states are identical or orthogonal in the case.

  相似文献   

2.
Any attempt to construct a realistinterpretation of quantum theory founders on theKochen–Specker theorem, which asserts theimpossibility of assigning values to quantum quantitiesin a way that preserves functional relations between them. We constructa new type of valuation which is defined on alloperators, and which respects an appropriate version ofthe functional composition principle. The truth-values assigned to propositions are (i) contextual and(ii) multivalued, where the space of contexts and themultivalued logic for each context come naturally fromthe topos theory of presheaves. The first step in our theory is to demonstrate that theKochen–Specker theorem is equivalent to thestatement that a certain presheaf defined on thecategory of self-adjoint operators has no globalelements. We then show how the use of ideas drawn from the theory ofpresheaves leads to the definition of a generalizedvaluation in quantum theory whose values are sieves ofoperators. In particular, we show how each quantum state leads to such a generalized valuation. Akey ingredient throughout is the idea that, in asituation where no normal truth-value can be given to aproposition asserting that the value of a physical quantity A lies in a subset , it is nevertheless possible toascribe a partial truth-value which is determined by theset of all coarse-grained propositions that assert thatsome function f(A) lies in f(), and that are true in a normalsense. The set of all such coarse-grainings forms asieve on the category of self-adjoint operators, and ishence fundamentally related to the theory ofpresheaves.  相似文献   

3.

The Kochen-Specker theorem is investigated for n spin-1/2 systems by using an inequality proposed in Nagata (J. Math. Phys. 46, 102101, 2005) on the basis on binary logic. A measurement theory based on the truth values (binary logic), i.e., the truth T (1) for true and the falsity F (0) for false is used. The values of measurement outcome are either + 1 or 0 (in \(\hbar /2\) unit). The quantum predictions by n-multipartite states violate the inequality by an amount that grows exponentially with n. The measurement theory based on the binary logic provides an exponentially stronger refutation of the existence of hidden-variable when the number of parties of the state increases more. It turns out that the Kochen-Specker theorem becomes a quite strong theorem when the dimension of the multipartite state highly increases, regardless of entanglement properties.

  相似文献   

4.
The well known Kochen-Specker’s theorem (Kochen and Specker J. Math. Mech. 17:59–87, 1967) is devoted to the problem of hidden variables in quantum mechanics. In the paper we present a geometric proof for an indefinite analogy of Kochen-Specker’s theorem. On the real three-dimensional Krein space there exists unique two-valued probability measure.  相似文献   

5.
We view DHR superselection sectors with finite statistics as Quantum Field Theory analogs of elliptic operators where KMS functionals play the role of the trace composed with the heat kernel regularization. We extend our local holomorphic dimension formula and prove an analogue of the index theorem in the Quantum Field Theory context. The analytic index is the Jones index, more precisely the minimal dimension, and, on a 4-dimensional spacetime, the DHR theorem gives the integrality of the index. We introduce the notion of holomorphic dimension; the geometric dimension is then defined as the part of the holomorphic dimension which is symmetric under charge conjugation. We apply the AHKT theory of chemical potential and we extend it to the low dimensional case, by using conformal field theory. Concerning Quantum Field Theory on a curved spacetime, the geometry of the manifold enters in the expression for the dimension. If a quantum black hole is described by a spacetime with bifurcate Killing horizon and sectors are localizable on the horizon, the variation of logarithm of the geometric dimension is proportional to the incremental free energy, due to the addition of the charge, and to the inverse temperature, hence to the inverse of the surface gravity in the Hartle–Hawking KMS state. For this analysis we consider a conformal net obtained by restricting the field to the horizon (“holography”). Compared with our previous work on Rindler spacetime, this result differs inasmuch as it concerns true black hole spacetimes, like the Schwarzschild–Kruskal manifold, and pertains to the entropy of the black hole itself, rather than of the outside system. An outlook concerns a possible relation with supersymmetry and noncommutative geometry. Received: 8 March 2000 / Accepted: 17 April 2001  相似文献   

6.
In this paper we introduce a minimal formal intuitionistic propositional Gentzen sequent calculus for handling quantum types, quantum storage being introduced syntactically along the lines of Girard's of course operator !. The intuitionistic fragment of orthologic is found to be translatable into this calculus by means of a quantum version of the Heyting paradigm. When realized in the category of finite dimensional Hilbert spaces, the familiar qubit arises spontaneously as the irreducible storage capable quantum computational unit, and the necessary involvement of quantum entanglement in the quantum duplication process is plainly and explicitly visible. Quantum computation is modelled by a single extra axiom, and reproduces the standard notion when interpreted in a larger category.  相似文献   

7.
In 1974 perfect crystal interferometry has been developed and immediately afterwards the 4π-symmetry of spinor wave-functions has been verified. The new method opened a new access to the observation of intrinsic quantum phenomena. Spin-superposition, quantum state reconstruction and quantum beat effects are examples of such investigations. In this connection efforts have been made to separate and measure various dynamical and geometrical phases. Non-cyclic and non-adiabatic topological phases have been identified and their stability against various fluctuations and dissipative forces has been investigated by means of ultra-cold neutrons. An entanglement between different degrees of freedom of a single neutron system demonstrated the contextuality feature of quantum mechanics. In its continuation this yields to Kochen-Specker theorem like investigations providing a new basis for information processing and for the understanding of quantum physics in general. All investigations show the equivalence of various phase spaces and show how physical phenomena are correlated by quantum laws. Some curiosa occurred during the experiments and some epistemological aspects will be discussed as well.  相似文献   

8.
A method of elaborating pulse sequences performing unitary transformations on the basis of their transformation matrices has been developed. For the first time the pulse protocols performing two-qubit quantum logical operations in electron spin systems have been obtained.  相似文献   

9.
Valuation functions of observables in quantum mechanics are often expected to obey two constraints called the sum rule and product rule. However, the Kochen-Specker (KS) theorem shows that for a Hilbert space of quantum mechanics of dimension d ≥ 3, these constraints contradict individually with the assumption of value definiteness. The two rules are not irrelated and Peres [Found. Phys. 26 (1996)807] has conceived a method of converting the product rule into a sum rule for the case of two qubits. Here we apply this method to a proof provided by Mermin based on the product rule for a three-qubit system involving nine operators. We provide the conversion of this proof to one based on sum rule involving ten operators.  相似文献   

10.
In this continuation of an earlier paper we develop further the theme of quantum logical specification and derive from it some apparently physically viable instantiations of potential quantum computing devices. Specifically, in the case of a one-parameter set of terms (or labels)—read as instants of time—we find, emerging quite naturally from the algebraic setup, the paradigm for a single qubit epitomized by the case of a two-state fermion interacting with an external single mode boson. This covers the cases: cavity QED, trapped ions, and, when the qubits are multiplexed appropriately, NMR based systems. (This case degenerates to one in which only bosons are relevant as in the case of pure bosonic harmonic oscillator models in the “dual rail” representation. Such models fly in the face of the logic itself, thus clearly revealing even at this level their well-known shortcomings as practical quantum computing devices. Here as elsewhere logical constraints apparently dominate physical ones.) In a final section we indicate briefly how this process exactly generalizes, in the case of a manifold of terms more general than the one-parameter case, to yield the notion of holonomic quantum computation. In the course of this investigation we find an interpretation of path integrals as limits of sequences of logical CUTS, thus establishing a link—though still tenuous—between ensembles of acts of quantum computation and Lagrangians.  相似文献   

11.
A diagrammatic representation is given of the 24 rays of Peres that makes it easy to pick out all the 512 parity proofs of the Kochen-Specker theorem contained in them. The origin of this representation in the four-dimensional geometry of the rays is pointed out.  相似文献   

12.
In this paper,the Virial Theorem based on a class of quantum nonlinear harmonic oscillators is presented.This relationship has to do with parameter λ and ∂/∂λ,where the λ is a real number.When λ=0,the nonlinear harmonic oscillator naturally reduces to the usual quantum linear harmonic oscillator,and the Virial Theorem also reduces to the usual Virial Theorem.  相似文献   

13.
In a previous paper, we proposed assigning asthe value of a physical quantity in quantum theory acertain kind of set (a sieve) of quantities that arefunctions of the given quantity. The motivation was in part physical — such a valuationilluminates the Kochen–Specker theorem — andin part mathematical — the valuation arisesnaturally in the topos theory of presheaves. This paperdiscusses the conceptual aspects of this proposal. We also undertake two othertasks. First, we explain how the proposed valuationscould arise much more generally than just in quantumphysics; in particular, they arise as naturally in classical physics. Second, we give anothermotivation for such valuations (that applies equally toclassical and quantum physics). This arises fromapplying to propositions about the values of physical quantities some general axioms governingpartial truth for any kind of proposition.  相似文献   

14.
Yu and Oh (eprint) [1] have given a state-independent proof of the Kochen-Specker theorem in three dimensions using only 13 rays. The proof consists of showing that a non-contextual hidden variable theory necessarily leads to an inequality that is violated by quantum mechanics. We give a similar proof making use of 21 rays that constitute a SIC (symmetric informationally-complete positive operator-valued measure) and a complete set of MUB (mutually unbiased bases). A theory-independent inequality is also presented using the same 21 rays, as required for experimental tests of contextuality.  相似文献   

15.
An orthomodular lattice (OML) with a conditional state can be used as a model for noncompatible events (a quantum system). In this paper we will study some properties of a conditional state and an s-map which are defined on an OML. We show conditions when a quantum system has the same properties as the classical probability space.  相似文献   

16.
An interpretation of quantum mechanics is discussed. It is assumed that quantum is energy. An algorithm by means of the energy interpretation is discussed. An algorithm, based on the energy interpretation, for fast determining a homogeneous linear function f(x) := s.x = s 1 x 1 + s 2 x 2 + ? + s N x N is proposed. Here x = (x 1, … , x N ), x j R and the coefficients s = (s 1, … , s N ), s j N. Given the interpolation values \((f(1), f(2),...,f(N))=\vec {y}\), the unknown coefficients \(s = (s_{1}(\vec {y}),\dots , s_{N}(\vec {y}))\) of the linear function shall be determined, simultaneously. The speed of determining the values is shown to outperform the classical case by a factor of N. Our method is based on the generalized Bernstein-Vazirani algorithm to qudit systems. Next, by using M parallel quantum systems, M homogeneous linear functions are determined, simultaneously. The speed of obtaining the set of M homogeneous linear functions is shown to outperform the classical case by a factor of N × M.  相似文献   

17.
We develop a synthesis of Turing's paradigm of computation and von Neumann's quantum logic to serve as a model for quantum computation with recursion, such that potentially non-terminating computation can take place, as in a quantum Turing machine. This model is based on the extension of von Neumann's quantum logic to partial states, defined here as sub-probability measures on the Hilbert space, equipped with the natural point-wise partial ordering. The sub-probability measures allow a certain probability for the non-termination of the computation. We then derive an extension of Gleason's theorem and show that, for Hilbert spaces of dimension greater than two, the partial order of sub-probability measures is order isomorphic with the collection of partial density operators, i.e. trace class positive operators with trace between zero and one, equipped with the usual partial ordering induced from positive operators. We show that the expected value of a bounded observable with respect to a partial state can be defined as a closed bounded interval, which extends the classical definition of expected value.  相似文献   

18.
陶勇 《理论物理通讯》2012,57(3):343-347
In this paper,we attempt to give a sufficient condition of guaranteeing the validity of the proof of the quantum adiabatic theorem.The new sufficient condition can clearly remove the inconsistency and the counterexample of the quantum adiabatic theorem pointed out by Marzlin and Sanders.  相似文献   

19.
An Ergodic Theorem for the Quantum Relative Entropy   总被引:1,自引:1,他引:0  
We prove the ergodic version of the quantum Steins lemma which was conjectured by Hiai and Petz. The result provides an operational and statistical interpretation of the quantum relative entropy as a statistical measure of distinguishability, and contains as a special case the quantum version of the Shannon-McMillan theorem for ergodic states. A version of the quantum relative Asymptotic Equipartition Property (AEP) is given.  相似文献   

20.
Unconditionally secure two-party bit commitment based solely on the principles of quantum mechanics (without exploiting special relativistic signalling constraints, or principles of general relativity or thermodynamics) has been shown to be impossible, but the claim is repeatedly challenged. The quantum bit commitment theorem is reviewed here and the central conceptual point, that an Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen attack or cheating strategy can always be applied, is clarified. The question of whether following such a cheating strategy can ever be disadvantageous to the cheater is considered and answered in the negative. There is, indeed, no loophole in the theorem.  相似文献   

设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号