首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
相似文献
 共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 15 毫秒
1.
The paper deals with a coding method for a sequent calculus of the propositional logic. The method is based on the sequent calculus. It allows us to determine if a formula is derivable in the calculus without constructing a derivation tree. The main advantage of the coding method is its compactness in comparison with derivation trees of the sequent calculus. The coding method can be used as a decision procedure for the propositional logic.  相似文献   

2.
In this paper, we consider branching time temporal logic CT L with epistemic modalities for knowledge (belief) and with awareness operators. These logics involve the discrete-time linear temporal logic operators “next” and “until” with the branching temporal logic operator “on all paths”. In addition, the temporal logic of knowledge (belief) contains an indexed set of unary modal operators “agent i knows” (“agent i believes”). In a language of these logics, there are awareness operators. For these logics, we present sequent calculi with a restricted cut rule. Thus, we get proof systems where proof-search becomes decidable. The soundness and completeness for these calculi are proved. Published in Lietuvos Matematikos Rinkinys, Vol. 47, No. 3, pp. 328–340, July–September, 2007.  相似文献   

3.
In this paper, we study the temporal logic S4Dbr with two temporal operators “always” and “eventually.” An equivalent sequent calculus is presented with formulae as modal clauses or modal clauses starting with operator “always.” An upper bound of deduction tree is given for propositional logic. A theorem prover for propositional logic is written in SWI-Prolog. Published in LietuvosMatematikos Rinkinys, Vol. 46, No. 2, pp. 203–214, April–June, 2006.  相似文献   

4.
Justification logics are modal-like logics that provide a framework for reasoning about justifications. This paper introduces labeled sequent calculi for justification logics, as well as for combined modal-justification logics. Using a method due to Sara Negri, we internalize the Kripke-style semantics of justification and modal-justification logics, known as Fitting models, within the syntax of the sequent calculus to produce labeled sequent calculi. We show that all rules of these systems are invertible and the structural rules (weakening and contraction) and the cut rule are admissible. Soundness and completeness are established as well. The analyticity for some of our labeled sequent calculi are shown by proving that they enjoy the subformula, sublabel and subterm properties. We also present an analytic labeled sequent calculus for S4LPN based on Artemov–Fitting models.  相似文献   

5.
In the paper, the first-order intuitionistic temporal logic sequent calculus LBJ is considered. The invertibility of some of the LBJ rules, syntactic admissibility of the structural rules and the cut rule in LBJ, as well as Harrop and Craig's interpolation theorems for LBJ are proved. Gentzen's midsequent theorem is proved for the LBJ' calculus which is obtained from LBJ by removing the antecedent disjunction rule from it. Published in Lietuvos Matematikos Rinkinys, Vol. 40, No. 3, pp. 255–276, July–September, 2000.  相似文献   

6.
We consider the formulas of pure hybrid logic without occurrences of a satisfaction operator. We describe a couple of formula derivation tactics in sequent calculus and prove the decidability of two classes of formulas. Decidable classes are obtained by setting restrictions on nominal occurrences in the formulas. Published in Lietuvos Matematikos Rinkinys, Vol. 44, No. 4, pp. 563–572, October–December, 2007.  相似文献   

7.
In this paper, we consider two logics of time and knowledge. These logics involve the discrete time linear temporal logic operators ``next' and ``until'. In addition, they contain an indexed set of unary epistemic modalities ``agent $i$ knows'. In these logics, the temporal and epistemic dimensions may interact. The particular interactions we consider capture perfect recall. We consider perfect recall in synchronously distributed systems and in systems without any assumptions. For these logics, we present sequent calculi with an analytic cut rule. Thus, we get proof systems where proof-search becomes decidable. The soundness and completeness of these calculi are proved.  相似文献   

8.
An infinitary calculus for a restricted fragment of the first-order linear temporal logic is considered. We prove that for this fragment one can construct the infinitary calculusG * without contraction on predicate formulas. The calculusG * possesses the following properties: (1) the succedent rule for the existential quantifier is included into the corresponding axiom; (2) the premise of the antecedent rule for the universal quantifier does not contain a duplicate of the main formula. The soundness and completness ofG * are also proved. Institute of Mathematics and Informatics, Akademijos 4, 2600 Vilnius, Lithuania. Translated from Lietuvos Matematikos Rinkinys, Vol. 39, No. 3, pp. 378–397, July–September, 1999. Translated by R. Lapinskas  相似文献   

9.
We consider classical, multisuccedent intuitionistic, and intuitionistic sequent calculi for propositional likelihood logic. We prove the admissibility of structural rules and cut rule, invertibility of rules, correctness of the calculi, and completeness of the classical calculus with respect to given semantics.__________Published in Lietuvos Matematikos Rinkinys, Vol. 45, No. 1, pp. 3–21, January–March, 2005.  相似文献   

10.
We consider propositional dynamic logic for agents. For this logic, we present a sequent calculus with a restricted cut rule and prove the soundness and completeness for the calculus.  相似文献   

11.
This paper presents a uniform and modular method to prove uniform interpolation for several intermediate and intuitionistic modal logics. The proof-theoretic method uses sequent calculi that are extensions of the terminating sequent calculus G4ip for intuitionistic propositional logic. It is shown that whenever the rules in a calculus satisfy certain structural properties, the corresponding logic has uniform interpolation. It follows that the intuitionistic versions of K and KD (without the diamond operator) have uniform interpolation. It also follows that no intermediate or intuitionistic modal logic without uniform interpolation has a sequent calculus satisfying those structural properties, thereby establishing that except for the seven intermediate logics that have uniform interpolation, no intermediate logic has such a sequent calculus.  相似文献   

12.
We introduce a new sequent calculus for KD 45 logic. A loop-check technique is used to determine whether a sequent derivable or not. We concentrate ourselves on the efficiency of the loop-check technique used. The efficiency is obtained by making the loop-check to act locally (then we need to check only one or two current sequents), instead of a global loop-check used in known works as [3]. Moreover, the sequent calculus introduced uses a marked operator □ to integrate loop-check into an inference rule. Besides the efficient loop-check used, the sequent calculus introduced produces smaller derivation trees that reduce the derivation time. We also prove a lemma which determines the maximal number of modality rule applications in one branch of a tree. Published in Lietuvos Matematikos Rinkinys, Vol. 46, No. 1, pp. 55–66, January–March, 2006.  相似文献   

13.
We consider a propositional dynamic logic for agents with interactions such as known commitment, no learning, and perfect recall. For this logic, we present a sequent calculus with a restricted cut rule and prove the soundness and completeness for the calculus.__________Published in Lietuvos Matematikos Rinkinys, Vol. 45, No. 2, pp. 261–269, April–June, 2005.  相似文献   

14.
Let LB be a sequent calculus of the first-order classical temporal logic TB with time gaps. Let, further, LBJ be the intuitionistic counterpart of LB. In this paper, we consider conditions under which a sequent is derivable in the calculus LBJ if and only if it is derivable in the calculus LB. Such conditions are defined for sequents with one formula in the succedent (purely Glivenko -classes) and for sequents with the empty succedent (Glivenko -classes).  相似文献   

15.
In a previous paper I laid the foundations of a covariant Hamiltonian framework for the calculus of variations in general. The purpose of the present work is to demonstrate, in the context of classical field theory, how this covariant Hamiltonian formalism may be space + time decomposed. It turns out that the resulting “instantaneous” Hamiltonian formalism is an infinite- dimensional version of Ostrogradski 's theory and leads to the standard symplectic formulation of the initial value problem. The salient features of the analysis are: (i) the instantaneous Hamiltonian formalism does not depend upon the choice of Lepagean equivalent; (ii) the space + time decomposition can be performed either before or after the covariant Legendre transformation has been carried out, with equivalent results; (iii) the instantaneous Hamiltonian can be recovered in natural way from the multisymplectic structure inherent in the theory; and (iv) the space + time split symplectic structure lives on the space of Cauchy data for the evolution equations, as opposed to the space of solutions thereof.  相似文献   

16.
The semantics of modal logics for reasoning about belief or knowledge is often described in terms of accessibility relations, which is too expressive to account for mere epistemic states of an agent. This paper proposes a simple logic whose atoms express epistemic attitudes about formulae expressed in another basic propositional language, and that allows for conjunctions, disjunctions and negations of belief or knowledge statements. It allows an agent to reason about what is known about the beliefs held by another agent. This simple epistemic logic borrows its syntax and axioms from the modal logic KD. It uses only a fragment of the S5 language, which makes it a two-tiered propositional logic rather than as an extension thereof. Its semantics is given in terms of epistemic states understood as subsets of mutually exclusive propositional interpretations. Our approach offers a logical grounding to uncertainty theories like possibility theory and belief functions. In fact, we define the most basic logic for possibility theory as shown by a completeness proof that does not rely on accessibility relations.  相似文献   

17.
A deduction-based decision procedure is presented for the nonperiodic D-sequents of the first-order linear temporal logic. The D-sequents are obtained from D 2-sequents [7], [8] by removing the periodicity condition. The deductive procedure proposed consists of decidable deductive procedures that replace infinitary and finitary induction rules for the temporal operator ``always'. The soundness and completeness of the deduction-based decision procedure proposed is proved.  相似文献   

18.
Illative combinatory logic consists of the theory of combinators or lambda calculus extended by extra constants (and corresponding axioms and rules) intended to capture inference. The paper considers 4 systems of illative combinatory logic that are sound for first-order propositional and predicate calculus. The interpretation from ordinary logic into the illative systems can be done in two ways: following the propositions-as-types paradigm, in which derivations become combinators, or in a more direct way, in which derivations are not translated. Both translations are closely related in a canonical way. In a preceding paper, Barendregt, Bunder and Dekkers, 1993, we proved completeness of the two direct translations. In the present paper we prove completeness of the two indirect translations by showing that the corresponding illative systems are conservative over the two systems for the direct translations. In another version, DBB (1997), we shall give a more direct completeness proof. These papers fulfill the program of Church and Curry to base logic on a consistent system of -terms or combinators. Hitherto this program had failed because systems of ICL were either too weak (to provide a sound interpretation) or too strong (sometimes even inconsistent). Received: February 15, 1996  相似文献   

19.
Sambin [6] proved the normalization theorem (Hauptsatz) for GL, the modal logic of provability, in a sequent calculus version called by him GLS. His proof does not take into account the concept of reduction, commonly used in normalization proofs. Bellini [1], on the other hand, gave a normalization proof for GL using reductions. Indeed, Sambin's proof is a decision procedure which builds cut-free proofs. In this work we formalize this procedure as a recursive function and prove its recursiveness in an arithmetically formalizable way, concluding that the normalization of GL can be formalized in PA. MSC: 03F05, 03B35, 03B45.  相似文献   

20.
In this article, we develop a Malliavin calculus associated to a time-continuous Markov chain with finite state space. We apply it to get a criterion of density for solutions of stochastic differential equation involving the Markov chain and also to compute greeks.  相似文献   

设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号