首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
相似文献
 共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 46 毫秒
1.
The stationary set splitting game is a game of perfect information of length ω1 between two players, unsplit and split, in which unsplit chooses stationarily many countable ordinals and split tries to continuously divide them into two stationary pieces. We show that it is possible in ZFC to force a winning strategy for either player, or for neither. This gives a new counterexample to Σ22 maximality with a predicate for the nonstationary ideal on ω1, and an example of a consistently undetermined game of length ω1 with payoff de.nable in the second‐order monadic logic of order. We also show that the determinacy of the game is consistent with Martin's Axiom but not Martin's Maximum. (© 2008 WILEY‐VCH Verlag GmbH & Co. KGaA, Weinheim)  相似文献   

2.
It is known that for a tridiagonal Toeplitz matrix, having on the main diagonal the constant a0 and on the two first off‐diagonals the constants a1(lower) and a−1(upper), which are all complex values, there exist closed form formulas, giving the eigenvalues of the matrix and a set of associated eigenvectors. For example, for the 1D discrete Laplacian, this triple is (a0,a1,a−1)=(2,−1,−1). In the first part of this article, we consider a tridiagonal Toeplitz matrix of the same form (a0,aω,aω), but where the two off‐diagonals are positioned ω steps from the main diagonal instead of only one. We show that its eigenvalues and eigenvectors can also be identified in closed form and that interesting connections with the standard Toeplitz symbol are identified. Furthermore, as numerical evidences clearly suggest, it turns out that the eigenvalue behavior of a general banded symmetric Toeplitz matrix with real entries can be described qualitatively in terms of the symmetrically sparse tridiagonal case with real a0, aω=aω, ω=2,3,…, and also quantitatively in terms of those having monotone symbols. A discussion on the use of such results and on possible extensions complements the paper.  相似文献   

3.
We prove a local normal form theorem of the Gaifman type for the infinitary logic Lω( Q u)ω whose formulas involve arbitrary unary quantifiers but finite quantifier rank. We use a local Ehrenfeucht‐Fraïssé type game similar to the one in [9]. A consequence is that every sentence of Lω( Q u)ω of quantifier rank n is equivalent to an infinite Boolean combination of sentences of the form (?iy)ψ(y), where ψ(y) has counting quantifiers restricted to the (2n–1 – 1)‐neighborhood of y. (© 2005 WILEY‐VCH Verlag GmbH & Co. KGaA, Weinheim)  相似文献   

4.
We study game formulas the truth of which is determined by a semantical game of uncountable length. The main theme is the study of principles stating reflection of these formulas in various admissible sets. This investigation leads to two weak forms of strict-II11 reflection (or ∑1-compactness). We show that admissible sets such as H2) and Lω2 which fail to have strict-II11 reflection, may or may not, depending on set-theoretic hypotheses satisfy one or both of these weaker forms. Mathematics Subject Classification : 03C70, 03C75.  相似文献   

5.
We show that there is a model of ZF in which the Borel hierarchy on the reals has length ω2. This implies that ω1 has countable cofinality, so the axiom of choice fails very badly in our model. A similar argument produces models of ZF in which the Borel hierarchy has exactly λ + 1 levels for any given limit ordinal λ less than ω2. We also show that assuming a large cardinal hypothesis there are models of ZF in which the Borel hierarchy is arbitrarily long. (© 2008 WILEY‐VCH Verlag GmbH & Co. KGaA, Weinheim)  相似文献   

6.
Let η be a regular cardinal. It is proved, among other things, that: (i) if J(η) is the corresponding long James space, then every closed subspace YJ(η), with Dens (Y) = η, has a copy of 𝓁2(η) complemented in J(η); (ii) if Y is a closed subspace of the space of continuous functions C([1, η]), with Dens (Y) = η, then Y has a copy of c0(η) complemented in C([1, η]). In particular, every nonseparable closed subspace of J1) (resp. C([1, ω1])) contains a complemented copy of 𝓁21) (resp.c01)). As consequence, we give examples (J1), C([1, ω1]), C(V), V being the “long segment”) of Banach spaces X with the hereditary density property (HDP) (i.e., for every subspace YX we have that Dens (Y) = w*–Dens (Y*)), in spite of these spaces are not weakly Lindelof determined (WLD).  相似文献   

7.
I introduced the notions of proper and piecewise proper families of reals to make progress on a long standing open question in the field of models of Peano Arithmetic [5]. A family of reals is proper if it is arithmetically closed and its quotient Boolean algebra modulo the ideal of finite sets is a proper poset. A family of reals is piecewise proper if it is the union of a chain of proper families each of whom has size ≤ ω1. Here, I investigate the question of the existence of proper and piecewise proper families of reals of different cardinalities. I show that it is consistent relative to ZFC to have continuum many proper families of cardinality ω1 and continuum many piecewise proper families of cardinality ω2 (© 2009 WILEY‐VCH Verlag GmbH & Co. KGaA, Weinheim)  相似文献   

8.
For a weight function ω and a closed set A ? ?N let ?(ω)(A) denote the space of all ω-Whitney jets of Beurling type on A. It is shown that for each closed set A ? ?N there exists an ω-extension operator EA: ?(ω)(A) → ?(ω)(?N) if and only if ω is a (DN)-function (see MEISE and TAYLOR [18], 3.3). Moreover for a fixed compact set K ? ?N there exists an ω-extension operator EK: ?(ω)(K) → ?(ω)(?N) if and only if the Fréchet space ?(ω)(K) satisfies the property (DN) (see Vogt [29], 1.1.).  相似文献   

9.
Let 1 < n < ω and β > n. We show that the class NrnCAβ of n‐dimensional neat reducts of β‐dimensional cylindric algebras is not closed under forming elementary subalgebras. This solves a long‐standing open problem of Tarski and his co‐authors Andréka, Henkin, Monk and Németi. The proof uses genuine model‐theoretic arguments.  相似文献   

10.
Let Sω and S2 denote the sequential fan and Arens' space, respectively. In this paper, we shall prove the following main results. (1) If Πi=1 Xi contains a copy of Sω (S2), then some Πni=1 Xi contains a copy of Sω (Sω or S2, respectively). (2) Let f: XY be a closed map such that any f-1(y) contains no closed copy of Sω (S2). If X contains a closed copy of Sω (S2), then Y contains a closed copy of Sω (Sω or S2, respectively).As applications of (1) and (2), we shall consider the Fréchet or strongly Fréchetness, or sequentiality of products of finitely or countably many spaces.  相似文献   

11.
Let S be a locally compact semigroup, let ω be a weight function on S, and let Ma (S, ω) be the weighted semigroup algebra of S. Let L0 (S;Ma (S, ω)) be the C*‐algebra of allMa (S, ω)‐measurable functions g on S such that g /ω vanishes at infinity. We introduce and study an Arens multiplication on L0 (S;Ma (S, ω))* under which Ma (S, ω) is a closed ideal. We show that the weighted measure algebra M (S, ω) plays an important role in the structure of L0 (S;Ma (S, ω))*. We then study Arens regularity of L0 (S;Ma (S, ω))* and ist relation with Arens regularity of Ma (S, ω), M (S, ω) and the discrete convolution algebra 1(S, ω). As the main result, we prove that L0 (S;Ma (S, ω))* is Arens regular if and only if S is finite, or S is discrete and Ω is zero cluster. (© 2008 WILEY‐VCH Verlag GmbH & Co. KGaA, Weinheim)  相似文献   

12.
In this article, a cut‐free system TLMω1 for infinitary propositional modal logic is proposed which is complete with respect to the class of all Kripke frames.The system TLMω1 is a kind of Gentzen style sequent calculus, but a sequent of TLMω1 is defined as a finite tree of sequents in a standard sense. We prove the cut‐elimination theorem for TLMω1 via its Kripke completeness.  相似文献   

13.
We provide a sharp, sufficient condition to decide if a point y on a convex surface S is a farthest point (i.e., is at maximal intrinsic distance from some point) on S, involving a lower bound π on the total curvature ωy at y, ωyπ. Further consequences are obtained when ωy > π, and sufficient conditions are derived to guarantee that a convex cap contains at least one farthest point. A connection between simple closed quasigeodesics O of S, points yS\O with ωy > π, and the set ?? of all farthest points on S, is also investigated (© 2009 WILEY‐VCH Verlag GmbH & Co. KGaA, Weinheim)  相似文献   

14.
《代数通讯》2013,41(8):2809-2825
Let k be a field and An(ω) be the Taft's n2-dimensional Hopf algebra. When n is odd, the Drinfeld quantum double D(An(ω)) of An(ω) is a ribbon Hopf algebra. In the previous articles, we constructed an n4-dimensional Hopf algebra Hn(p, q) which is isomorphic to D(An(ω)) if p ≠ 0 and q = ω?1 , and studied the irreducible representations of Hn(1, q) and the finite dimensional representations of H3(1, q). In this article, we examine the finite-dimensional representations of Hn(l q), equivalently, of D(An(ω)) for any n ≥ 2. We investigate the indecomposable left Hn(1, q)-module, and describe the structures and properties of all indecomposable modules and classify them when k is algebraically closed. We also give all almost split sequences in mod Hn(1, q), and the Auslander-Reiten-quiver of Hn(1 q).  相似文献   

15.
Let G be a connected graph with odd girth 2κ+1. Then G is a (2κ+1)‐angulated graph if every two vertices of G are connected by a path such that each edge of the path is in some (2κ+1)‐cycle. We prove that if G is (2κ+1)‐angulated, and H is connected with odd girth at least 2κ+3, then any retract of the box (or Cartesian) product GH is ST where S is a retract of G and T is a connected subgraph of H. A graph G is strongly (2κ+1)‐angulated if any two vertices of G are connected by a sequence of (2κ+1)‐cycles with consecutive cycles sharing at least one edge. We prove that if G is strongly (2κ+1)‐angulated, and H is connected with odd girth at least 2κ+1, then any retract of GH is ST where S is a retract of G and T is a connected subgraph of H or |V(S)|=1 and T is a retract of H. These two results improve theorems on weakly and strongly triangulated graphs by Nowakowski and Rival [Disc Math 70 ( 13 ), 169–184]. As a corollary, we get that the core of the box product of two strongly (2κ+1)‐angulated cores must be either one of the factors or the box product itself. Furthermore, if G is a strongly (2κ+1)‐angulated core, then either Gn is a core for all positive integers n, or the core of Gn is G for all positive integers n. In the latter case, G is homomorphically equivalent to a normal Cayley graph [Larose, Laviolette, Tardiff, European J Combin 19 ( 12 ), 867–881]. In particular, let G be a strongly (2κ+1)‐angulated core such that either G is not vertex‐transitive, or G is vertex‐transitive and any two maximum independent sets have non‐empty intersection. Then Gn is a core for any positive integer n. On the other hand, let Gi be a (2κi+1)‐angulated core for 1 ≤ in where κ1 < κ2 < … < κn. If Gi has a vertex that is fixed under any automorphism for 1 ≤ in‐1, or Gi is vertex‐transitive such that any two maximum independent sets have non‐empty intersection for 1 ≤ in‐1, then □i=1n Gi is a core. We then apply the results to construct cores that are box products with Mycielski construction factors or with odd graph factors. We also show that K(r,2r+1) □ C2l+1 is a core for any integers lr ≥ 2. It is open whether K(r,2r+1) □ C2l+1 is a core for r > l ≥ 2. © 2006 Wiley Periodicals, Inc. J Graph Theory  相似文献   

16.
A Banach space X is said to have the alternative Daugavet property if for every (bounded and linear) rank‐one operator T: XX there exists a modulus one scalar ω such that ∥Id+ωT ∥ = 1 + ∥T ∥. We give geometric characterizations of this property in the setting of C *‐algebras, JB *‐triples, and of their isometric preduals. (© 2008 WILEY‐VCH Verlag GmbH & Co. KGaA, Weinheim)  相似文献   

17.
We give a new proof of the strong partition relation on ω1, assuming the axiom of determinacy, which uses only a general argument not involving the complete analysis of a measure on ω1. (© 2003 WILEY‐VCH Verlag GmbH & Co. KGaA, Weinheim)  相似文献   

18.
We study ω‐categorical weakly o‐minimal expansions of Boolean lattices. We show that a structure ?? = (A,≤, ?) expanding a Boolean lattice (A,≤) by a finite sequence I of ideals of A closed under the usual Heyting algebra operations is weakly o‐minimal if and only if it is ω‐categorical, and hence if and only if A/I has only finitely many atoms for every I ∈ ?. We propose other related examples of weakly o‐minimal ω‐categorical models in this framework, and we examine the internal structure of these models.  相似文献   

19.
We show that certain properties of dimension complemented cylindric algebras, concerning neat embeddings, do not generalize much further. Let αω. There are non‐isomorphic representable cylindric algebras of dimension α each of which is a generating subreduct of the same β dimensional cylindric algebra. We also show that there exists a representable cylindric algebra ?? of dimension α, such that ?? is a generating subreduct of ?? and ??′, both in CAα +ω , however ?? and ??′ are not isomorphic. This settle questions raised by Henkin, Monk and Tarski (© 2009 WILEY‐VCH Verlag GmbH & Co. KGaA, Weinheim)  相似文献   

20.
设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号