共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 15 毫秒
1.
Javier Kalhat 《Acta Analytica》2008,23(2):161-176
In this paper I argue against Armstrong’s recent truthmaking account of possibility. I show that the truthmaking account presupposes
modality in a number of different ways, and consequently that it is incapable of underwriting a genuine reduction of modality.
I also argue that Armstrong’s account faces serious difficulties irrespective of the question of reduction; in particular,
I argue that his Entailment and Possibility Principles are both false.
相似文献
Javier KalhatEmail: |
2.
Paul Pollack 《Central European Journal of Mathematics》2011,9(2):294-301
In 1909, Hilbert proved that for each fixed k, there is a number g with the following property: Every integer N ≥ 0 has a representation in the form N = x 1 k + x 2 k + … + x g k , where the x i are nonnegative integers. This resolved a conjecture of Edward Waring from 1770. Hilbert’s proof is somewhat unsatisfying, in that no method is given for finding a value of g corresponding to a given k. In his doctoral thesis, Rieger showed that by a suitable modification of Hilbert’s proof, one can give explicit bounds on the least permissible value of g. We show how to modify Rieger’s argument, using ideas of F. Dress, to obtain a better explicit bound. While far stronger bounds are available from the powerful Hardy-Littlewood circle method, it seems of some methodological interest to examine how far elementary techniques of this nature can be pushed. 相似文献
3.
Jeppe Berggreen Høj 《Acta Analytica》2010,25(3):299-316
In this paper, I examine an account of instrumental reasoning recently put forth by John Broome. His key suggestion is that anyone who engages in reasoning about his intentions also believes that he will do what he intends to do and that combined with a belief about necessary means this creates rational pressure towards believing that one will take the necessary means. I argue that Broome’s model has three significant problems; his key premise is false—the sincere expression of an intention does not entail the belief that one will successfully execute that intention; his account yields a model of instrumental reasoning that is uncomfortably reflective; he seems unable to explain the rational pressure towards taking necessary means that arises directly from having an end and an instrumental belief. All three problems, I argue, are a consequence of Broome’s inadequate position on what it is to intend to do something. 相似文献
4.
5.
Mathematical Notes - Continued fractions with rational partial quotients arise in a natural way in the course of applying any $$k$$ -ary gcd algorithm to the ratio of natural numbers $$a$$ , $$b$$... 相似文献
6.
Simpson’s paradox reminds people that the statistical inference in a low-dimensional space probably distorts the reality in a high one seriously.To study the paradox with respect to Yule’s measure, this paper discusses simple collapsibility, strong collapsibility and consecutive collapsibility, and presents necessary and sufficient conditions of them.In fact, these conditions are of great importance for observational and experimental designs, eliminating confounding bias, categorizing discrete variables and so on. 相似文献
7.
We present a new approach to Berndtssons complex extension of Prékopas theorem. This approach is inspired by the recent local proof of Prékopas theorem obtained by Ball, Barthe and Naor. In the complex setting, this approach leads to a formula expressing in terms of (derivatives of) where e–(z)= As a consequence, we obtain new conditions ensuring that is subharmonic when is plurisubharmonic. 相似文献
8.
9.
10.
11.
Zhengyu Mao 《Mathematische Zeitschrift》2012,271(1-2):593-609
We prove a relation between Whittaker functionals of cusp forms on ${{\widetilde{SL}}_2}$ and the toric periods of forms on the quaternion algebra. As an application we prove a generalization of a formula of Gross. 相似文献
12.
14.
We obtain probability combinatorial inequalities for independent random variables, strengthening the well-known Rosenthal inequality. As a corollary, we prove that the generalized Rosenthal inequality for identically distributed independent functions remains valid in the case of quasinormed symmetric spaces. 相似文献
15.
V. Kargin 《Probability Theory and Related Fields》2013,157(3-4):575-604
It is shown that the normalized fluctuations of Riemann’s zeta zeros around their predicted locations follow the Gaussian law. It is also shown that fluctuations of two zeros, $\gamma _{k}$ and $\gamma _{k+x},$ with $x\sim \left( \log k\right) ^{\beta }, \beta >0,$ for large $k$ follow the two-variate Gaussian distribution with correlation $\left( 1-\beta \right) _{+}\! .$ 相似文献
16.
Mathematical Notes - Voronin’s theorem states that the Riemann zeta-function ζ(s) is universal in the sense that all analytic functions that are defined and have no zeros on the right... 相似文献
17.
《Expositiones Mathematicae》2023,41(1):238-243
We give a new elementary proof of the parallelizability of closed orientable 3-manifolds. We use as the main tool the fact that any such manifold admits a Heegaard splitting. 相似文献
18.
It is known that Goertzels algorithm is much less numerically accurate than the Fast Fourier Transform (FFT) (cf. [2]). In order to improve accuracy we propose modifications of both Goertzels and Horners algorithms based on the divide-and-conquer techniques. The proof of the numerical stability of these two modified algorithms is given. The numerical tests in Matlab demonstrate the computational advantages of the proposed modifications. The appendix contains the proof of numerical stability of Goertzels algorithm of polynomial evaluation.
AMS subject classification 65F35, 65G50 相似文献
19.
20.