首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
相似文献
 共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 343 毫秒
1.
The main result of the present article is the following: Let N be an infinite subset of , , and let be a matrix with infinitely many rows of completely Ramsey subsets of such that for every n, . Then there exist , a sequence of nonempty finite subsets of N, and an infinite subset T of such that for every infinite subset I of . We also give an application of this result to partitions of an uncountable analytic subset of a Polish space X into sets belonging to the σ‐algebra generated by the analytic subsets of X.  相似文献   

2.
Suppose that P is a forcing notion, L is a language (in ), a P‐name such that “ is a countable L‐structure”. In the product , there are names such that for any generic filter over , and . Zapletal asked whether or not implies that there is some such that . We answer this question negatively and discuss related issues.  相似文献   

3.
We develop an approach to the longstanding conjecture of Kierstead concerning the character of strongly nontrivial automorphisms of computable linear orderings. Our main result is that for any η‐like computable linear ordering , such that has no interval of order type η, and such that the order type of is determined by a ‐limitwise monotonic maximal block function, there exists computable such that has no nontrivial automorphism.  相似文献   

4.
We show how one can obtain solutions to the Arzelà‐Ascoli theorem using suitable applications of the Bolzano‐Weierstraß principle. With this, we can apply the results from 10 and obtain a classification of the strength of instances of the Arzelà‐Ascoli theorem and a variant of it. Let be the statement that each equicontinuous sequence of functions contains a subsequence that converges uniformly with the rate and let be the statement that each such sequence contains a subsequence which converges uniformly but possibly without any rate. We show that is instance‐wise equivalent, over , to the Bolzano‐Weierstraß principle and that is instance‐wise equivalent, over , to , and thus to the strong cohesive principle (). Moreover, we show that over the principles , and are equivalent.  相似文献   

5.
Let denote a first‐order logic in a language that contains infinitely many constant symbols and also containing intuitionistic logic . By , we mean the associated logic axiomatized by the double negation of the universal closure of the axioms of plus . We shall show that if is strongly complete for a class of Kripke models , then is strongly complete for the class of Kripke models that are ultimately in .  相似文献   

6.
We show:
  1. The Boolean Prime Ideal theorem is equivalent to each one of the statements:
    1. For every family of compact spaces, for every family of basic closed sets of the product with the fip there is a family of subbasic closed sets () with the fip such that for every ”.
    2. For every compact Loeb space (the family of all non empty closed subsets of has a choice function) and for every set X the product is compact”.
  2. (: the axiom of choice restricted to families of finite sets) implies “every well ordered product of cofinite topologies is compact” and “every well ordered basic open cover of a product of cofinite topologies has a finite subcover”.
  3. (: the axiom of choice restricted to countable families of finite sets) iff “every countable product of cofinite topologies is compact”.
  4. (: every filter of extends to an ultrafilter) is equivalent to the proposition “for every compact Loeb space having a base of size and for every set X of size the product is compact”.
  相似文献   

7.
Let κ be an arbitrary regular infinite cardinal and let denote the set of κ‐maximal cofinitary groups. We show that if holds and C is a closed set of cardinals such that
  • 1. , ,
  • 2. if then ,
  • 3. ,
then there is a generic extension in which cofinalities have not been changed and such that . The theorem generalizes a result of Brendle, Spinas and Zhang (cf. 4 ) regarding the possible sizes of maximal cofinitary groups. Our techniques easily modify to provide analogous results for the spectra of maximal κ‐almost disjoint families in , maximal families of κ‐almost disjoint permutations on κ and maximal families of κ‐almost disjoint functions in . In addition we construct a κ‐Cohen indestructible κ‐maximal cofinitary group and so establish the consistency of , which for is due to Yi Zhang (cf. 10 ).  相似文献   

8.
A theorem, proven in the present author's Master's thesis 2 states that a real number is ‐computable, whenever its continued fraction is in (the third Grzegorczyk class). The aim of this paper is to settle the matter with the converse of this theorem. It turns out that there exists a real number, which is ‐computable, but its continued fraction is not primitive recursive, let alone in . A question arises, whether some other natural condition on the real number can be combined with ‐computability, so that its continued fraction has low complexity. We give two such conditions. The first is ‐irrationality, based on a notion of Péter, and the second is polynomial growth of the terms of the continued fraction. Any of these two conditions, combined with ‐computability gives an (elementary) continued fraction. We conclude that all irrational algebraic real numbers and the number π have continued fractions in . All these results are generalized to higher levels of Grzegorczyk's hierarchy as well.  相似文献   

9.
In set theory without the Axiom of Choice , we study the deductive strength of the statements (“Every partially ordered set without a maximal element has two disjoint cofinal subsets”), (“Every partially ordered set without a maximal element has a countably infinite disjoint family of cofinal subsets”), (“Every linearly ordered set without a maximum element has two disjoint cofinal subsets”), and (“Every linearly ordered set without a maximum element has a countably infinite disjoint family of cofinal subsets”). Among various results, we prove that none of the above statements is provable without using some form of choice, is equivalent to , + (Dependent Choices) implies , does not imply in (Zermelo‐Fraenkel set theory with the Axiom of Extensionality modified in order to allow the existence of atoms), does not imply in (Zermelo‐Fraenkel set theory minus ) and (hence, ) is strictly weaker than in .  相似文献   

10.
In this paper, notions of ‐like and c0‐like equivalence relations are introduced. We characterize the positions of ‐like and c0‐like equivalence relations in the Borel reducibility hierarchy by comparing them with equivalence relations and .  相似文献   

11.
We show:
  • (i) iff every countable product of sequential metric spaces (sequentially closed subsets are closed) is a sequential metric space iff every complete metric space is Cantor complete.
  • (ii) Every infinite subset X of has a countably infinite subset iff every infinite sequentially closed subset of includes an infinite closed subset.
  • (iii) The statement “ is sequential” is equivalent to each one of the following propositions:
  • (a) Every sequentially closed subset A of includes a countable cofinal subset C,
  • (b) for every sequentially closed subset A of , is a meager subset of ,
  • (c) for every sequentially closed subset A of , ,
  • (d) every sequentially closed subset of is separable,
  • (e) every sequentially closed subset of is Cantor complete,
  • (f) every complete subspace of is Cantor complete.
  相似文献   

12.
Martin's Axiom is the statement that for every well‐ordered cardinal , the statement holds, where is “if is a c.c.c. quasi order and is a family of dense sets in P, then there is a ‐generic filter of P”. In , the fragment is provable, but not in general in . In this paper, we investigate the interrelation between and various choice principles. In the choiceless context, it makes sense to drop the requirement that the cardinal κ be well‐ordered, and we can define for any (not necessarily well‐ordered) cardinal the statement to be “if is a c.c.c. quasi order with , and is a family of dense sets in P, then there is a ‐generic filter of P”. We then define to be the statement that for every (not necessarily well‐ordered) cardinal , we have that holds. We then investigate the set‐theoretic strength of the principle .  相似文献   

13.
Our main results are: (A) It is consistent relative to a large cardinal that holds but fails. (B) If holds and are two infinite cardinals such that and λ carries a good scale, then holds. (C) If are two cardinals such that κ is λ‐Shelah and , then there is no good scale for λ.  相似文献   

14.
For an uncountable cardinal κ, let be the assertion that every ω1‐stationary preserving poset of size is semiproper. We prove that is a strong principle which implies a strong form of Chang's conjecture. We also show that implies that is presaturated.  相似文献   

15.
A paraconsistent modal‐like logic, , is defined as a Gentzen‐type sequent calculus. The modal operator in the modal logic can be simulated by the paraconsistent double negation in . Some theorems for embedding into a Gentzen‐type sequent calculus for and vice versa are proved. The cut‐elimination and completeness theorems for are also proved.  相似文献   

16.
In this paper we characterize the strong reflecting property for ‐cardinals for all , characterize Harrington's Principle and its generalization and discuss the relationship between the strong reflecting property for ‐cardinals and Harrington's Principle .  相似文献   

17.
For a signature L with at least one constant symbol, an L‐structure is called minimal if it has no proper substructures. Let be the set of isomorphism types of minimal L‐structures. The elements of can be identified with ultrafilters of the Boolean algebra of quantifier‐free L‐sentences, and therefore one can define a Stone topology on . This topology on generalizes the topology of the space of n‐marked groups. We introduce a natural ultrametric on , and show that the Stone topology on coincides with the topology of the ultrametric space iff the ultrametric space is compact iff L is locally finite (that is, L contains finitely many n‐ary symbols for any ). As one of the applications of compactness of the Stone topology on , we prove compactness of certain classes of metric spaces in the Gromov‐Hausdorff topology. This slightly refines the known result based on Gromov's ideas that any uniformly totally bounded class of compact metric spaces is precompact.  相似文献   

18.
In this paper, the inconsistency lemmas of intuitionistic and classical propositional logic are formulated abstractly. We prove that, when a (finitary) deductive system is algebraized by a variety , then has an inconsistency lemma—in the abstract sense—iff every algebra in has a dually pseudo‐complemented join semilattice of compact congruences. In this case, the following are shown to be equivalent: (1)  has a classical inconsistency lemma; (2)  has a greatest compact theory and is filtral, i.e., semisimple with EDPC; (3) the compact congruences of any algebra in form a Boolean lattice; (4) the compact congruences of any constitute a Boolean sublattice of the full congruence lattice of . These results extend to quasivarieties and relative congruences. Except for (2), they extend even to protoalgebraic logics, with deductive filters in the role of congruences. A protoalgebraic system with a classical inconsistency lemma always has a deduction‐detachment theorem (DDT), while a system with a DDT and a greatest compact theory has an inconsistency lemma. The converses are false.  相似文献   

19.
Working with uncountable structures of fixed cardinality, we investigate the complexity of certain equivalence relations and show that if , then many of them are ‐complete, in particular the isomorphism relation of dense linear orders. Then we show that it is undecidable in whether or not the isomorphism relation of a certain well behaved theory (stable, NDOP, NOTOP) is ‐complete (it is, if , but can be forced not to be).  相似文献   

20.
In this paper, we prove a definable version of Kirszbraun's theorem in a non‐Archimedean setting for definable families of functions in one variable. More precisely, we prove that every definable function , where and , that is λ‐Lipschitz in the first variable, extends to a definable function that is λ‐Lipschitz in the first variable.  相似文献   

设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号