首页 | 本学科首页   官方微博 | 高级检索  
相似文献
 共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 328 毫秒
1.
It is shown that the ring of two 2×2 generic matrices over a field has infinite global dimension. It is also proved that there is a non-free projective module over that ring. Finally, the authors show that the trace ring of that generic matrix ring is an iterated Ore extension from which it follows that the trace ring has global dimension five and that the finitely-generated projective modules are stably free.  相似文献   

2.
Previous authors have shown that if demand that cannot be filled from stock is partially backordered, then using the full-backordering model or assuming that all stockouts will result in lost sales can lead to substantial increases in cost relative to using a model that specifically recognizes the percentage of the stockouts that will be backordered. The models that these authors developed resulted in procedures or equations that are relatively difficult to use. In this paper we take a different approach to modeling the deterministic EOQ with partial backordering that results in equations that are more like the comparable equations for the basic EOQ and its full-backordering extension.  相似文献   

3.
The publication of Davidson 2001, anthologizing articles from the 1980s and 1990s, encourages reconsidering arguments contained in them. One such argument is Davidson’s omniscient-interpreter argument (‘OIA’) in Davidson 1983. The OIA allegedly establishes that it is necessary that most beliefs are true. Thus the omniscient interpreter, revived in 2001 and now 20 years old, was born to answer the skeptic. In Part I of this paper, I consider charges that the OIA establishes only that it is possible that most beliefs are true; if correct, then it is also possibly the case that most beliefs are false—the skeptic’s very position. Next, I consider two responses on Davidson’s behalf, showing that each fails. In Part II, I show that the OIA establishes neither that it is necessarily merely possibly but actually the case that most beliefs are true. I then conclude that this is enough to answer the skeptic.  相似文献   

4.
This article addresses and attempts to refute several of the most widespread and enduring misconceptions held by students regarding the enterprise of science. The ten myths discussed include the common notions that theories become laws, that hypotheses are best characterized as educated guesses, and that there is a commonly-applied scientific method. In addition, the article includes discussion of other incorrect ideas such as the view that evidence leads to sure knowledge, that science and its methods provide absolute proof, and that science is not a creative endeavor. Finally, the myths that scientists are objective, that experiments are the sole route to scientific knowledge and that scientific conclusions are continually reviewed conclude this presentation. The paper ends with a plea that instruction in and opportunities to experience the nature of science are vital in preservice and inservice teacher education programs to help unseat the myths of science.  相似文献   

5.
Sean Crawford 《Acta Analytica》2003,18(30-31):193-216
This paper argues that Twin Earth twins belong to the same psychological natural kind, but that the reason for this is not that the causal powers of mental states supervene on local neural structure. Fodor’s argument for this latter thesis is criticized and found to rest on a confusion between it and the claim that Putnamian and Burgean type relational psychological properties do not affect the causal powers of the mental states that have them. While it is true that Putnamian and Burgean type relational psychological properties do not affect causal powers, it is false that no relational psychological properties do. Examples of relational psychological properties that do affect causal powers are given and psychological laws are sketched that subsume twins in virtue of them instantiating these relational properties rather than them sharing the narrow contents of their thoughts.  相似文献   

6.
The first stage in hierarchical approaches to Floorplan Design defines topological relations between components that intend to optimize a given objective in a circuit board. These relations determine a placement that is subsequently optimized in order to minimize a cost measurement (that will probably be one between chip area or perimeter). The board optimization gives rise to multiple subproblems that need to be answered in order to obtain a good solution. Among the most relevant ones we find the problem of defining the optimal orientation of cells and the definition of the optimal cutting sequence that minimize the placement board area. We will present a generalization of an algorithm due to Stockmeyer so that it obtains a solution that not only defines the optimal cell orientation but also the slicing cuts sequence that will lead to this optimal orientation and overall area minimization.  相似文献   

7.
A ring R is a QB-ring provided that aR bR=R with a,b∈R implies that there exists a y∈R such that a by∈R_q~(-1).It is said that a ring R is a JB-ring provided that R/J(R)is a QB-ring,where J(R)is the Jacobson radical of R.In this paper,various necessary and sufficient conditions,under which a ring is a JB-ring,are established.It is proved that JB-rings can be characterized by pseudo-similarity.Furthermore,the author proves that R is a JB-ring iff so is R/J(R)~2.  相似文献   

8.
A stage structured host-parasitoid model is derived and the equilibria studied. It is shown under what conditions the parasitoid controls an exponentially growing host in the sense that a coexistence equilibrium exists. Furthermore, for host populations whose inherent growth rate is not too large it is proved that in order to minimize the adult host equilibrium level it is necessary that the parasitoids attack only one of the larval stages. It is also proved in this case that the minimum adult host equilibrium level is attained when the parasitoids attack that larval stage which also maximizes the expected number of emerging adult parasitoid per larva at equilibrium. Numerical simulations tentatively indicate that the first conclusion remains in general valid for the model. However, numerical studies also show that it is not true in general that the optimal strategy will maximize the number of emerging adult parasitoid per larva at equilibrium.  相似文献   

9.
We study the structure of projections of finite cutting paths that correspond to a Sturmian substitution with incidence matrix that has determinant 1. We show that such projections can be seen as two-letter words, and that there exists another Sturmian substitution that generates these words.  相似文献   

10.
We study the family of graphs whose number of primitive cycles equals its cycle rank. It is shown that this family is precisely the family of ring graphs. Then we study the complete intersection property of toric ideals of bipartite graphs and oriented graphs. An interesting application is that complete intersection toric ideals of bipartite graphs correspond to ring graphs and that these ideals are minimally generated by Gröbner bases. We prove that any graph can be oriented such that its toric ideal is a complete intersection with a universal Gröbner basis determined by the cycles. It turns out that bipartite ring graphs are exactly the bipartite graphs that have complete intersection toric ideals for any orientation.  相似文献   

11.
Following criticism from proponents of workstation group support systems about the lack of validity of ‘wide-band’ group support systems (GSS), a recent article argued that it was inappropriate to attempt to establish the level of experimental validity for such GSS that is demanded by researchers working with 'narrow-band' GSS. It was argued that ‘wide-band’ and workstation GSS are very different and this means that it is unlikely that the same measures of success would be appropriate. This paper agrees with this view but not with its extension, that the overall validation requirement is different; theoretical validity is a necessary feature of a full evaluation but it is not sufficient by itself - experimental validity must also be sought. This paper argues against the view that since experimental validity cannot be obtained, theoretical validity will suffice. A twin-track research approach involving theoretical and experimental validity is proposed that can unite researchers investigating (almost) all forms of GSS, modelled on the PIMS programme and supported by one of the research frameworks that already exist.  相似文献   

12.
We show that there exists a family of instances of the lot-sizing problem, such that any branch-and-bound tree that solves them requires an exponential number of nodes, even in the case when the branchings are performed on general split disjunctions. This result is of interest since there exists dynamic programming algorithm that solves lot-sizing in polynomial-time. To the best of our knowledge, this is the first study that shows that dynamic programming can be exponentially faster than branch-and-bound.  相似文献   

13.
Coherentists on epistemic justification claim that all justification is inferential, and that beliefs, when justified, get their justification together (not in isolation) as members of a coherent belief system. Some recent work in formal epistemology shows that “individual credibility” is needed for “witness agreement” to increase the probability of truth and generate a high probability of truth. It can seem that, from this result in formal epistemology, it follows that coherentist justification is not truth-conducive, that it is not the case that, under the requisite conditions, coherentist justification increases the probability of truth and generates a high probability of truth. I argue that this does not follow.  相似文献   

14.
The examination of now-abandoned behaviorist analysis of the concept of belief can bring to light defects in perspectives such as functionalism and physicalism that are still considered viable. Most theories have in common that they identify the holding of the belief that p by a subject S with some matter of fact in or about S that is distinct from and independent of p. In the case of behaviorism it is easy to show that this feature of the theory generates incoherence in the first-person point of view since it gives footing to the possibility that S could correctly assert “I believe that p,” (that is, “I have the complex disposition the behaviorist theory identifies with holding the belief that p”) and at the same time deny that p is the case. Parallel incoherence can be developed in the context of other philosophically popular accounts of the nature of belief.  相似文献   

15.
In this paper, I examine an account of instrumental reasoning recently put forth by John Broome. His key suggestion is that anyone who engages in reasoning about his intentions also believes that he will do what he intends to do and that combined with a belief about necessary means this creates rational pressure towards believing that one will take the necessary means. I argue that Broome’s model has three significant problems; his key premise is false—the sincere expression of an intention does not entail the belief that one will successfully execute that intention; his account yields a model of instrumental reasoning that is uncomfortably reflective; he seems unable to explain the rational pressure towards taking necessary means that arises directly from having an end and an instrumental belief. All three problems, I argue, are a consequence of Broome’s inadequate position on what it is to intend to do something.  相似文献   

16.
This paper investigates properties of a parametric set defined by finitely many equality and inequality constraints under the constant rank constraint qualification (CRCQ). We show, under the CRCQ, that the indicator function of this set is prox-regular with compatible parametrization, that the set-valued map that assigns each parameter to the set defined by that parameter satisfies a continuity property similar to the Aubin property, and that the Euclidean projector onto this set is a piecewise smooth function. We also show in the absence of parameters that the CRCQ implies the Mangasarian-Fromovitz constraint qualification to hold in some alternative expression of the set.  相似文献   

17.
In 1970 it was proved that a square cannot be cut into an odd number of triangles of equal areas. In 1990 it was proved that any centrally symmetric polygon has that property. In the present paper we propose a broad generalization, which would also imply that any polygon whose edges are parallel to the x - or y -axes has that property. We prove that the generalization holds for polygons with at most six sides. Received November 24, 1999, and in revised form January 28, 2000.  相似文献   

18.
Summary. When numerically integrating time-dependent differential equations, it is often recommended to employ methods that preserve some of the invariant quantities (mass, energy, etc.) of the problem being considered. This recommendation is usually justified on the grounds that conservation of invariant quantities may ensure that the numerical solution possesses some important qualitative features. However there are cases where schemes that preserve invariants are also advantageous in that they possess favourable error propagation mechanisms that render them superior from a quantitative point of view. In the present paper we consider the Korteweg-de Vries equation as a case study. We show rigorously that, for soliton problems and at leading order, the error of conservative schemes consists of a phase error that grows linearly with time plus a complementary term that is bounded in the norm uniformly in time. For ‘general’, nonconservative schemes the error involves a linearly growing amplitude error, a quadratically growing phase error and a complementary term that grows linearly in the norm. Numerical experiments are presented. Received November 21, 1994 / Revised version received July 17, 1995  相似文献   

19.
For a semisimple factorizable Hopf algebra over a field of characteristic zero, we show that the value that an integral takes on the inverse Drinfel’d element differs from the value that it takes on the Drinfel’d element itself by at most a fourth root of unity. This can be reformulated by saying that the central charge of the Hopf algebra is an integer. If the dimension of the Hopf algebra is odd, we show that these two values differ by at most a sign, which can be reformulated by saying that the central charge is even. We give a precise condition on the dimension that determines whether the plus sign or the minus sign occurs. To formulate our results, we use the language of modular data.  相似文献   

20.
In this paper I defend epistemic circularity by arguing that the “No Self-Support” principle (NSS) is false. This principle, ultimately due to Fumerton (1995), states that one cannot acquire a justified belief in the reliability of a source of belief by trusting that very source. I argue that NSS has the skeptical consequence that the trustworthiness of all of our sources ultimately depends upon the trustworthiness of certain fundamental sources – sources that we cannot justifiably believe to be reliable. This is a problem, I claim, because if the trustworthiness of all of our sources depends upon sources that we should not believe to be reliable, then a reflective individual should not trust any of his sources at all. The hidden cost of rejecting epistemic circularity is thus the unacceptable skeptical thesis that reflective individuals like you and I have no justified beliefs whatsoever.  相似文献   

设为首页 | 免责声明 | 关于勤云 | 加入收藏

Copyright©北京勤云科技发展有限公司  京ICP备09084417号